Learn About the Law
Get help with your legal needs
FindLaw’s Learn About the Law features thousands of informational articles to help you understand your options. And if you’re ready to hire an attorney, find one in your area who can help.
Ivan ANTONYUK, Corey Johnson, Alfred Terrille, Joseph Mann, Leslie Leman, Lawrence Sloane, Plaintiffs-Appellees, v. Steven G. JAMES, in his official capacity as the Superintendent of the New York State Police, Matthew J. Doran, in his official capacity as the Licensing Official of Onondaga County, Joseph Cecile, in his Official Capacity as the Chief of Police of Syracuse, Defendants-Appellants, Kathleen Hochul, in her official capacity as the Governor of the State of New York, William Fitzpatrick, in his official capacity as the Onondaga County District Attorney, Eugene Conway, in his official capacity as the Sheriff of Onondaga County, P. David Soares, in his official capacity as the District Attorney of Albany County, Gregory Oakes, in his official capacity as the District Attorney of Oswego County, Don Hilton, in his official capacity as the Sheriff of Oswego County, Joseph Stanzione, in his official capacity as the District Attorney of Greene County, Defendants.
Contents
BACKGROUND․––––
I. Regulatory Background․––––
A. Licensing․––––
B. Sensitive Locations․––––
C. Restricted Locations․––––
II. Procedural History․––––
III. Legal Standards Governing the Right to Keep and Bear Arms․––––
A. Heller․––––
B. McDonald․––––
C. Post-Heller and -McDonald Circuit Precedent․––––
D. Bruen․––––
E. Rahimi․––––
F. History and Tradition․––––
LICENSING REGIME․––––
I. Overview․––––
II. Standing․––––
III. Merits․––––
A. The Character Requirement․––––
1. Facial Second Amendment Challenge․––––
2. Historical Challenge to Licensing Officer Discretion․––––
3. Bruen-Based Challenge to Licensing-Officer Discretion․––––
B. The Catch-All․––––
C. The Cohabitant Requirement․––––
D. The Social Media Requirement․––––
SENSITIVE LOCATIONS․––––
I. Treatment Centers․––––
A. Standing․––––
B. Merits․––––
1. District Court Decision․––––
2. The State's Historical Analogues․––––
a. Well-Established and Representative․––––
b. Consistency with Tradition․––––
3. Proper Analysis of Proffered Analogues․––––
II. Places of Worship․––––
A. Standing and Mootness․––––
B. Vacatur of Preliminary Injunctions․––––
III. Parks and Zoos․––––
A. Standing․––––
B. Merits․––––
1. District Court Decision․––––
a. Public Parks․––––
b. Zoos․––––
2. Analysis of the Historical Analogues — Public Parks․––––
a. Well-Established and Representative․––––
b. Consistency with Tradition․––––
3. Analysis of the Historical Analogues — Zoos․––––
a. Well-Established and Representative․––––
b. Consistency with Tradition․––––
IV. Premises Licensed for Alcohol Consumption․––––
A. District Court Decision․––––
B. The State's Historical Analogues․––––
1. Well-Established and Representative․––––
2. Consistency with Tradition․––––
V. Theaters, Conference Centers, and Banquet Halls․––––
A. Justiciability․––––
B. Merits․––––
1. District Court Decision․––––
2. The State's Historical Analogues․––––
VI. First Amendment Gatherings․––––
A. Mann․––––
B. Terrille․––––
RESTRICTED LOCATIONS․––––
I. Standing․––––
II. Merits․––––
A. The District Court Decision․––––
B. Merits Analysis․––––
1. Scope of Second Amendment․––––
2. The State's Analogues on Appeal․––––
CONCLUSION․––––
In this case, heard and originally decided in tandem with three related cases, Plaintiffs raise First and Second Amendment challenges to many provisions of New York's laws regulating the public carriage of firearms. Below, the U.S. District Court for the Northern District of New York (Suddaby, J.) enjoined enforcement of more than a dozen such provisions. In the three related cases, the U.S. District Court for the Western District of New York (Sinatra, J.) separately enjoined a subset of the laws previously enjoined in Antonyuk, though based on slightly different reasoning. We stayed the various injunctions in all four cases pending appeal, expedited the appeals, and in light of the substantial overlap among the cases, heard argument in tandem on March 20, 2023.
On December 8, 2023, in a lengthy and detailed opinion, we AFFIRMED the injunctions in part, VACATED them in part, and REMANDED the cases to the district courts for further proceedings consistent with that opinion. In summary, we upheld the district courts’ injunctions with respect to N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(o)(iv) (social media disclosure); N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-d (restricted locations) as applied to private property held open to the general public; and N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-e(2)(c) as applied to certain plaintiffs in one of the consolidated cases. We vacated the injunctions in all other respects, having concluded either that the district court lacked jurisdiction or that the challenged laws do not violate the Constitution on their face. The plaintiffs in Antonyuk—but not those in the other three cases—then petitioned the Supreme Court for certiorari.
On June 21, 2024, the Supreme Court decided United States v. Rahimi, 602 U.S. ----, 144 S. Ct. 1889, 219 L.Ed.2d 351 (2024), and upheld the facial constitutionality of 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(8), which criminalizes the possession of firearms by certain individuals subject to domestic violence restraining orders. In the wake of Rahimi, the Supreme Court granted certiorari in Antonyuk, summarily vacated our judgment in that case, and remanded the case to this Court for further consideration in light of Rahimi. Antonyuk v. James, ––– U.S. ––––, 144 S. Ct. 2709, ––– L.Ed.2d –––– (2024). At the same time, the Court vacated seven other decisions regarding the Second Amendment from a variety of state and federal courts and remanded them all for further consideration.
As further detailed below, Rahimi involved a regulation of firearms that is quite different from any of those at issue in the present case, and thus has little direct bearing on our conclusions. Specifically, the complaint before us does not challenge a criminal prohibition of firearms possession by a particular class of individuals based on a prior judicial adjudication. Instead, it concerns facial challenges, not all of which are rooted solely in the Second Amendment,1 to a “shall issue” licensing regime for firearm possession, and to restrictions on firearm possession in certain sensitive locations. 2 The Court addressed neither issue in Rahimi.
However, the Court's analysis of the considerations and methodology bearing on the constitutionality of the statute before it, and in particular its explication of the role of history in interpreting the Second Amendment, clarified to some degree the meaning and effect of its prior decision in New York State Rifle & Pistol Association, Inc. v. Bruen, 597 U.S. 1, 142 S.Ct. 2111, 213 L.Ed.2d 387 (2022). For the most part, the methodology adopted in Rahimi is consonant with the one that we applied in our prior consolidated opinion, and the Court's analysis in Rahimi therefore supports our prior conclusions. In any event, we have conscientiously followed the Court's mandate and have reconsidered all of our conclusions in light of Rahimi, after receiving supplemental briefing from the parties on that decision. In consequence of our reconsideration, we now issue the following revised opinion in this case,3 taking account of the Supreme Court's latest guidance.
Accordingly, we AFFIRM the injunction in part, VACATE it in part, and REMAND the case to the district court for further proceedings consistent with the present opinion.
BACKGROUND
Plaintiffs are six individuals who raise numerous challenges to provisions of New York's Concealed Carry Improvement Act (“CCIA”), primarily on Second Amendment grounds. We begin with a description of that statute and then outline the Plaintiffs’ challenges in the district court and the issues on appeal. Because the Second Amendment dominates this appeal, we conclude this background section with a discussion of the Supreme Court's four 21st-century precedents addressing that Amendment: District of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570, 128 S.Ct. 2783, 171 L.Ed.2d 637 (2008); McDonald v. City of Chicago, 561 U.S. 742, 130 S.Ct. 3020, 177 L.Ed.2d 894 (2010); Bruen, 597 U.S. 1, 142 S.Ct. 2111, 213 L.Ed.2d 387; and Rahimi, ––– U.S. ––––, 144 S. Ct. 1889, 219 L.Ed.2d 351.
I. Regulatory Background
New York adopted the CCIA in the wake of the Supreme Court's decision in Bruen, which struck down New York's former “proper cause” requirement for carrying concealed firearms. 597 U.S. at 11, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Beginning with passage of the Sullivan Law in 1911 and its subsequent amendments, see 1911 N.Y. Laws ch. 195, § 1, p. 443; 1913 N.Y. Laws ch. 608, § 1, p. 1629, New York conditioned the right to carry a concealed firearm in public on a license that could be obtained only if the applicant demonstrated “good moral character” and a “proper cause” to carry the firearm “without regard to employment or place of possession,” N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(b), (2)(f) (effective Apr. 3, 2021, to July 5, 2022). Proper cause was defined as “a special need for self-protection distinguishable from that of the general community or of persons engaged in the same profession.” In re Klenosky, 75 A.D.2d 793, 793, 428 N.Y.S.2d 256 (1980), aff'd, 53 N.Y.2d 685, 439 N.Y.S.2d 108, 421 N.E.2d 503 (1981). No such proper cause was required to possess a firearm at one's home. N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(2)(a) (effective Apr. 3, 2021, to July 5, 2022).4 An applicant for an in-home license needed only to show good moral character and to satisfy certain other statutory requirements, such as being at least 21 years old and having no felony convictions. Id. § 400.00(1)(a)–(c), (2)(a).
Addressing only New York's proper-cause requirement, the Supreme Court in Bruen held that that requirement violated the Second Amendment because there was no 18th- or 19th-century tradition of conditioning the right to carry a firearm in public on a state official's assessment of special need or justification. 597 U.S. at 34–35, 70, 142 S.Ct. 2111. “We know of no other constitutional right,” the Supreme Court explained, whose exercise depends on an individual “demonstrating to government officers some special need.” Id. at 70, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
Following the decision in Bruen, New York Governor Kathy Hochul convened an Extraordinary Legislative Session, see N.Y. Const. art. IV, § 3 (authorizing the governor “to convene the legislature, or the senate only, on extraordinary occasions”), during which the New York legislature passed the CCIA. Signed into law on July 1, 2022, the CCIA amended various firearms-related provisions of New York's Penal Law, General Business Law, Executive Law, and State Finance Law. This appeal concerns the CCIA's Penal Law amendments related to “licensing,” “sensitive locations,” and “restricted locations.”
A. Licensing
Under the CCIA, applicants for both in-home and concealed-carry licenses must have “good moral character” to obtain a license. N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(b) (2023). The CCIA defines “good moral character” as “the essential character, temperament and judgement necessary to be entrusted with a weapon and to use it only in a manner that does not endanger oneself or others.” Id. As noted above, the “good moral character” requirement for both in-home and concealed-carry licenses pre-dates Bruen and the CCIA, but that standard had not previously been defined by statute. See § 400.00(1)(b) (effective Apr. 3, 2021, to July 5, 2022).
The CCIA added other relevant requirements that are particular to the issuance of concealed-carry licenses. An applicant for a concealed-carry license must attend an in-person meeting with a licensing officer and disclose to the officer: (1) the “names and contact information for the applicant's current spouse, or domestic partner, any other adults residing in the applicant's home, including any adult children of the applicant, and whether or not there are minors residing, full time or part time, in the applicant's home”; (2) the “names and contact information of ․ four character references who can attest to the applicant's good moral character”; (3) a list of all former and current social media accounts from the preceding three years; and (4) such other information as the licensing officer may require “that is reasonably necessary and related to the review of the licensing application.” Id. § 400.00(1)(o)(i)–(ii), (iv)–(v).
The applicant must also provide the licensing officer with a certificate verifying that he has completed certain required training. Id. § 400.00(1)(o)(iii). To obtain a concealed-carry license, the applicant must “complete an in-person live firearms safety course conducted by a duly authorized instructor with curriculum approved by the division of criminal justice services and the superintendent of state police.” Id. § 400.00(19). Among other things, the course must provide “a minimum of sixteen hours of in-person live curriculum” addressing various specified topics, like general firearm safety, safe-storage requirements, situational awareness, conflict de-escalation and management, the use of deadly force, and suicide prevention. Id. § 400.00(19)(a)(i)–(ii), (iv)–(v), (viii)–(x). The course must also provide “a minimum of two hours of a live-fire range training.” Id. § 400.00(19)(b). To obtain a certificate of completion, the applicant must pass a written test and show proficiency in live-fire range training. Id. § 400.00(19).
B. Sensitive Locations
The CCIA makes it a crime to carry a firearm in several “sensitive locations,” even for individuals with concealed-carry licenses. N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-e(1); cf. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (recognizing a “longstanding” tradition of “laws forbidding the carrying of firearms in sensitive places such as schools and government buildings” (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783)). The CCIA designates twenty categories of places as sensitive locations. N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-e(2)(a)–(t). For example, firearms are prohibited in “any place owned or under the control of federal, state or local government, for the purpose of government administration, including courts,” id. § 265.01-e(2)(a); in nursery schools, preschools, public schools, and certain licensed private schools, § 265.01-e(2)(f), (m); and in “any location being used as a polling place,” id. § 265.01-e(2)(q). More relevant to this appeal, an individual may not carry a firearm in “any location providing health, behavioral health, or chemical depend[e]nce care or services,” id. § 265.01-e(2)(b); any place of worship, id. § 265.01-e(2)(c); zoos and public parks, id. § 265.01-e(2)(d); any place holding a license for on-premise alcohol consumption, id. § 265.01-e(2)(o); “any place used for ․ performance, art[,] entertainment, gaming, or sporting events such as theaters, ․ conference centers, [and] banquet halls,” id. § 265.01-e(2)(p); and “any gathering of individuals to collectively express their constitutional rights to protest or assemble,” id. § 265.01-e(2)(s).5
C. Restricted Locations
In addition to prohibiting the carriage of firearms in any designated sensitive location, the CCIA makes it a crime to possess firearms in a “restricted location”:
A person is guilty of criminal possession of a weapon in a restricted location when such person possesses a firearm, rifle, or shotgun and enters into or remains on or in private property where such person knows or reasonably should know that the owner or lessee of such property has not permitted such possession by clear and conspicuous signage indicating that the carrying of firearms, rifles, or shotguns on their property is permitted or has otherwise given express consent.
N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-d(1) (2023). It is undisputed that the restricted-locations provision effectively prohibits entrance with a firearm onto another person's private property—whether that property is generally open to the public, like a gas station or grocery store, or is generally closed to the public, like a personal residence—unless the owner or lessee of the property provides affirmative, express consent to armed entry. Id.
II. Procedural History
On September 20, 2022, six individual Plaintiffs sued several defendants in their official capacity in the United States District Court for the Northern District of New York, challenging aspects of the CCIA's licensing, sensitive-locations, and restricted-locations provisions. The Plaintiffs are Ivan Antonyuk, Corey Johnson, Alfred Terrille, Joseph Mann, Leslie Leman, and Lawrence Sloane. Sloane, the only Plaintiff who does not already have a concealed-carry license, brought a Second Amendment challenge to the character, in-person interview, disclosure, and firearm-training requirements of the CCIA licensing regime. The other five Plaintiffs challenged certain of the CCIA's sensitive-locations provisions on Second Amendment grounds. All six Plaintiffs challenged the CCIA's restricted-locations provision on First Amendment compelled-speech and Second Amendment grounds. Altogether, the Plaintiffs sued Governor Hochul, Steven A. Nigrelli, the then-Superintendent of the New York State Police,6 and various local officials responsible for enforcing the CCIA in their respective jurisdictions: Matthew J. Doran, the licensing official of Onondaga County; William Fitzpatrick, the District Attorney of Onondaga County; Eugene Conway, the Sheriff of Onondaga County; Joseph Cecile, the Chief of Police of Syracuse; P. David Soares, the District Attorney of Albany County; Gregory Oakes, the District Attorney of Oswego County; Don Hilton, the Sheriff of Oswego County; and Joseph Stanzione, the District Attorney of Greene County.
On September 22, 2022, Plaintiffs moved for preliminary injunctive relief. On November 7, 2022, the district court (Suddaby, J.) granted their motion in part and denied it in part. See Antonyuk v. Hochul, 639 F. Supp. 3d 232, 349 (N.D.N.Y. 2022).
First, the court held that Sloane had standing to challenge the CCIA's licensing requirements, id. at 261; that each Plaintiff had standing to challenge the restricted-locations provision, id. at 293–94; and that at least one Plaintiff had standing to challenge the following sensitive-location provisions: (1) any location providing behavioral health or chemical dependence care or services; (2) any place of worship; (3) public playgrounds, public parks, and zoos; (4) nursery schools and preschools; (5) buses and airports; (6) any place that is licensed for on-premise alcohol consumption; (7) theaters, conference centers, and banquet halls; and (8) any gathering of individuals to collectively express their constitutional rights to protest or assemble, id. at 266–67, 269–72, 275, 282–83, 285, 288, 291–92.7
Second, the court held that the CCIA violated the Second Amendment by conditioning the issuance of a license on an applicant's good moral character and disclosure of a list of the applicant's current spouse and all adult cohabitants, a list of all former and current social media accounts from the preceding three years, and such other information as the licensing officer may require. Id. at 305, 308, 311–12. The court declined, however, to enjoin the requirements that an applicant attend an in-person meeting, provide four character references, and undergo firearms training. Id. at 306–07, 314, 316. Sloane does not challenge the latter aspects of the district court's decision.
Third, the court enjoined the sensitive-locations provisions as applied to each place that a Plaintiff had standing to challenge except for polling places, public areas restricted from general public access for a limited time by a governmental entity, public playgrounds, nursery schools, and preschools. Id. at 288, 327–28, 349. Plaintiffs do not challenge the court's refusal to enjoin the CCIA's enforcement as to those five places.
Fourth, and finally, the court enjoined the restricted-locations provision in its entirety on First Amendment compelled-speech and Second Amendment grounds. Id. at 340–47, 78–85.
Altogether, the district court enjoined the CCIA's:
(1) licensing requirements that
(a) an applicant have good moral character and
(b) disclose to a licensing officer
(i) a list of the applicant's current spouse and all adult cohabitants,
(ii) a list of all former and current social media accounts from the preceding three years, and
(iii) such other information as the officer may require;
(2) sensitive-locations provisions concerning
(a) locations providing behavioral health or chemical dependence care or services;
(b) places of worship;
(c) public parks and zoos;
(d) buses and airports;
(e) places that are licensed for on-premise alcohol consumption;
(f) theaters, conference centers, and banquet halls; and
(g) gatherings of individuals to collectively express their constitutional rights to protest or assemble; and
(3) restricted-locations provision.
The State timely appealed and moved this Court for a stay pending appeal, which was granted. The State challenged each aspect of the injunction except for the portion concerning the CCIA's application to buses and airports. No Plaintiff cross-appealed or otherwise challenged any aspect of the district court's decision adverse to them.
On December 8, 2023, we issued a consolidated opinion in this case and the three related cases—Spencer, Christian, and Hardaway, see supra note 3. As relevant to Antonyuk, we upheld the district court's injunction with respect to N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(o)(iv) (social media disclosure) and N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-d (restricted locations) as applied to private property held open to the general public. We vacated the injunction in all other respects.8
The Plaintiffs then petitioned the Supreme Court for certiorari. Their petition chiefly raised two issues: (1) whether, when conducting Bruen’s history and tradition analysis for Second Amendment challenges, see infra Background § III.F, courts must rely exclusively on historical evidence from the Founding; and (2) whether our vacatur of the injunction of the CCIA's “good moral character” requirement contravened the Bruen framework. See generally Petition for Writ of Certiorari, Antonyuk, ––– U.S. ––––, 144 S. Ct. 2709, ––– L.Ed.2d –––– (2024) (No. 23-910) (hereinafter, “Petition for Cert.”). After the Supreme Court decided Rahimi, it granted the Plaintiffs’ petition, vacated our prior judgment in this case, and remanded the case for further consideration in light of that opinion. Rahimi expressly declined to reach the first issue raised in Plaintiffs’ petition for certiorari. See Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1898 n.1. As for the second issue, Rahimi adds to the relevant body of precedent to consider when analyzing Second Amendment challenges, and we have done so, as reflected in this amended opinion.
III. Legal Standards Governing the Right to Keep and Bear Arms
With that background, we now outline the Supreme Court's quartet of 21st-century cases interpreting the right to keep and bear arms: District of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570, 128 S.Ct. 2783, 171 L.Ed.2d 637 (2008); McDonald v. City of Chicago, 561 U.S. 742, 130 S.Ct. 3020, 177 L.Ed.2d 894 (2010); New York State Rifle & Pistol Association, Inc. v. Bruen, 597 U.S. 1, 142 S.Ct. 2111, 213 L.Ed.2d 387 (2022); and United States v. Rahimi, 602 U.S. ––––, 144 S. Ct. 1889, 219 L.Ed.2d 351 (2024). We also outline our former circuit precedent and the historical framework that we understand Supreme Court precedent requires be applied to Second and Fourteenth Amendment challenges asserting the right to keep and bear arms.
A. Heller
The Second Amendment provides: “A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed.” U.S. Const. amend. II. In Heller, the Supreme Court held for the first time that the Second Amendment codifies a pre-existing individual right to keep and bear arms for self-defense in case of confrontation—a right that is not limited to service in an organized militia. 554 U.S. at 592, 595, 128 S.Ct. 2783.9
But that right, the Court twice cautioned, is “not unlimited,” just as no other right in the Bill of Rights is unlimited. Id. at 595, 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783. Historically, “the right was not a right to keep and carry any weapon whatsoever in any manner whatsoever and for whatever purpose.” Id. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783. Nor has the right ever been understood to “protect those weapons not typically possessed by law-abiding citizens for lawful purposes.” Id. at 625, 128 S.Ct. 2783. Stated differently, the Second Amendment protects the right to keep and bear “the sorts of weapons” that are “ ‘in common use’ ”—a “limitation [that] is fairly supported by the historical tradition of prohibiting the carrying of ‘dangerous and unusual weapons.’ ” Id. at 627, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (first quoting United States v. Miller, 307 U.S. 174, 179, 59 S.Ct. 816, 83 L.Ed. 1206 (1939); then quoting 4 Commentaries on the Laws of England 148–49 (1769)). And, the Court made clear, “nothing in [its] opinion should be taken to cast doubt on longstanding prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons and the mentally ill, or laws forbidding the carrying of firearms in sensitive places such as schools and government buildings, or laws imposing conditions and qualifications on the commercial sale of arms.” Id. at 626–27, 128 S.Ct. 2783. The Court identified those “regulatory measures” as “presumptively lawful,” noting too that those “examples” were not an “exhaustive” list of constitutional regulations governing firearms. Id. at 627, 128 S.Ct. 2783 n.26.
Ultimately, however, the Court had no occasion to “undertake an exhaustive historical analysis ․ of the full scope of the Second Amendment.” Id. at 626. At issue in Heller was a District of Columbia law that “totally ban[ned] handgun possession in the home” and “require[d] ․ any lawful firearm in the home [to] be disassembled or bound by a trigger lock at all times, rendering it inoperable.” Id. at 628, 128 S.Ct. 2783. The Court held that that requirement was a major intrusion on “the inherent right of self-defense,” because “[t]he handgun ban amount[ed] to a prohibition of an entire class of ‘arms’ that is overwhelmingly chosen by American society for that lawful purpose,” and because the “prohibition extend[ed] ․ to the home, where the need for defense of self, family, and property is most acute.” Id. “Under any of the standards of scrutiny that [the Court] ha[s] applied to enumerated constitutional rights,” the challenged District of Columbia law “would fail constitutional muster.” Id. at 628–29, 128 S.Ct. 2783. The Second Amendment, if nothing else, “elevates above all other interests the right of law-abiding, responsible citizens to use arms in defense of hearth and home.” Id. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783.
Heller did not offer much guidance to lower courts analyzing future Second Amendment claims. There would come a day, the Court explained, for it to “expound upon the historical justifications for the exceptions [it had] mentioned if and when those exceptions come before [it].” Id. But the Court ruled out the standard of rational-basis review, id. at 628, 128 S.Ct. 2783 n.27, or an “interest-balancing inquiry” that assesses the proportionality of the law's burden to the state's interest, id. at 634, 128 S.Ct. 2783, because no other enumerated constitutional right is subject to such standards, id. at 628 n.27, 634–35, 128 S.Ct. 2783.
B. McDonald
Two years later came McDonald, which held that the Second Amendment is “fully applicable to the States.” 561 U.S. at 750, 130 S.Ct. 3020. A plurality reached that conclusion via the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, id. at 791, 130 S.Ct. 3020 (plurality opinion), while Justice Thomas reached the same conclusion relying on the Privileges or Immunities Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, id. at 806, 130 S.Ct. 3020 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment).
Like Heller, McDonald did not survey the full scope of the Second Amendment. But the plurality instructed that the Second Amendment is not “subject to an entirely different body of rules than the other Bill of Rights guarantees.” Id. at 780, 130 S.Ct. 3020 (plurality opinion). And incorporating the Second Amendment to apply to the States, the Supreme Court assured us, would “not imperil every law regulating firearms”:
It is important to keep in mind that Heller, while striking down a law that prohibited the possession of handguns in the home, recognized that the right to keep and bear arms is not “a right to keep and carry any weapon whatsoever in any manner whatsoever and for whatever purpose.” We made it clear in Heller that our holding did not cast doubt on such longstanding regulatory measures as “prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons and the mentally ill,” “laws forbidding the carrying of firearms in sensitive places such as schools and government buildings, or laws imposing conditions and qualifications on the commercial sale of arms.” We repeat those assurances here.
Id. at 786 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 626–27, 128 S.Ct. 2783). McDonald also repeated Heller’s clarification that “self-defense [i]s ‘the central component of the right itself.’ ” Id. at 787, 130 S.Ct. 3020 (emphasis in original) (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 599, 128 S.Ct. 2783).
C. Post-Heller and -McDonald Circuit Precedent
In the wake of Heller and McDonald, this Circuit, as well as every other regional circuit,10 employed a two-part test to assess Second Amendment challenges. E.g., Libertarian Party of Erie County v. Cuomo, 970 F.3d 106, 118 (2d Cir. 2020). At step one, we asked whether a challenged law burdened conduct that fell within the scope of the Second Amendment based on its text and history. Id. If so, we proceeded to step two, assessing whether the challenged law burdened the core of the Second Amendment, defined by Heller as self-defense in the home. Id. at 119. If the burden was de minimis, the law was subject to intermediate scrutiny; if the burden was substantial and affected the core of the right, the law was subject to strict scrutiny. Id. at 119, 128.
For example, applying that two-part test in Kachalsky v. County of Westchester, we upheld New York State's proper-cause requirement to obtain a license to carry a concealed firearm outside the home without regard to employment or place of possession. 701 F.3d 81, 101 (2d Cir. 2012). As noted, an applicant had proper cause for such a license if he had “a special need for self-protection distinguishable from that of the general community or of persons engaged in the same profession.” Klenosky, 75 A.D.2d at 793, 428 N.Y.S.2d 256. In Kachalsky, we assumed the first step of the two-part test in favor of the challenger: specifically, that the Second Amendment protects the right to keep and bear arms outside the home. 701 F.3d at 89, 93. Indeed, all we could tell from Heller and McDonald was “that Second Amendment guarantees are at their zenith within the home,” and “[w]hat we d[id] not know [wa]s the scope of that right beyond the home and the standards for determining when and how the right can be regulated by a government.” Id. at 89 (emphasis added). Proceeding to step two, we assessed the proper-cause requirement under intermediate scrutiny, because that requirement did not burden the core right of armed self-defense in the home. Id. at 94–96. We upheld the requirement under intermediate scrutiny because New York had “substantial, indeed compelling, governmental interests in public safety and crime prevention,” id. at 97, and because a limitation on “handgun possession in public to those who have a reason to possess the weapon for a lawful purpose is substantially related” to that interest, id. at 98.
Later, in Libertarian Party of Erie County, we upheld New York's character requirement, which at that time was statutorily undefined, against a facial challenge. 970 F.3d at 127–28. We acknowledged that the requirement “affect[ed] the core Second Amendment right” identified in Heller because it prohibited individuals lacking good moral character from possessing firearms for self-defense in the home. Id. at 127. But the requirement “d[id] not burden the ability of ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens to use arms in defense of hearth and home.’ ” Id. (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783). We therefore applied intermediate scrutiny because “the conditions placed on the core Second Amendment right [we]re not onerous.” Id. at 127–28. Applying intermediate scrutiny, we found that the challenger's complaint itself “reveal[ed] a close relationship between the licensing regime and the State's interests in public safety and crime prevention—as well as solicitude for the Second Amendment rights of citizens who are responsible and law abiding.” Id. at 128.
D. Bruen
Fourteen years after Heller and twelve years after McDonald, the Supreme Court decided Bruen, abrogating our circuit precedent, both the specific holding of Kachalsky and the general approach we took to Second Amendment claims.
Bruen rejected step two of “the predominant framework” described above and set out a new “test rooted in the Second Amendment's text, as informed by history.” 597 U.S. at 19, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Thus, a court must now consider whether “the Second Amendment's plain text covers an individual's conduct.” Id. at 24, 142 S.Ct. 2111. If so, “the Constitution presumptively protects that conduct.” Id. To overcome that presumption, “[t]he government must then justify its regulation by demonstrating that it is consistent with the Nation's historical tradition of firearm regulation.” Id. Stated differently, “the government must affirmatively prove that its firearms regulation is part of the historical tradition that delimits the outer bounds of the right to keep and bear arms.” Id. at 19. Bruen therefore sets out a two-step framework, with the first step based on text and the second step based on history.11
Applying that two-step framework, the Supreme Court struck down New York's proper-cause requirement. First, the Court held that the plain text of the Second Amendment protected the petitioners’ right to carry handguns outside the home. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 32–33, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Like the challengers in Heller and McDonald, the petitioners were “ordinary, law-abiding, adult citizens” and “part of ‘the people’ whom the Second Amendment protects,” id. at 31–32, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 580, 128 S.Ct. 2783), and they wished to carry handguns that were “weapons ‘in common use’ today for self-defense,” id. at 32, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 627, 128 S.Ct. 2783). The Court also held that the Second Amendment protected their right to carry those firearms outside the home: the Second Amendment does not draw a “home/public distinction”; the word “ ‘bear’ naturally encompasses public carry” because even though people “keep” firearms in their homes, they do not typically “ ‘bear’ (i.e., carry) them in the home beyond moments of actual confrontation”; and “confining the right to ‘bear’ arms to the home would make little sense” because self-defense is central to the right and “[m]any Americans hazard greater danger outside the home than in it.” Id. at 32–33, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
Second, New York failed to demonstrate that the proper-cause requirement was consistent with the Nation's historical tradition of firearm regulation. Id. at 70, 142 S.Ct. 2111. In reaching that conclusion, the Court emphasized the exceptional nature of the proper-cause requirement. “We know of no other constitutional right that an individual may exercise only after demonstrating to government officers some special need.” Id. Historically, only two states, Texas and West Virginia, had laws in the late-19th century that remotely resembled New York's proper-cause requirement, and those states “ ‘contradict[ed] the overwhelming weight of other evidence regarding the right to keep and bear arms for defense’ in public.” Id. at 66, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 632, 128 S.Ct. 2783). The overwhelming weight of the historical evidence revealed that legislatures did not require a showing of special need to exercise the right to public carry but instead enacted laws that “limited the intent for which one could carry arms, the manner by which one carried arms, or the exceptional circumstances under which one could not carry arms, such as before justices of the peace and other government officials.” Id. at 70, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Thus, the Second Amendment does not tolerate a “may issue” licensing regime, like New York's former regime, that conditions the issuance of a concealed-carry license on a discretionary assessment of need or justification. Id. at 71, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
The Court, however, made clear that “nothing in [its] analysis should be interpreted to suggest the unconstitutionality of the ․ ‘shall-issue’ licensing regimes” applicable in 43 States. Id. at 38, 142 S.Ct. 2111 n.9. In “ ‘shall issue’ jurisdictions,’ ” licensing “authorities must issue concealed-carry licenses whenever applicants satisfy certain threshold requirements.” Id. at 13, 142 S.Ct. 2111. “Because these licensing regimes do not require applicants to show an atypical need for armed self-defense, they do not necessarily prevent ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens’ from exercising their Second Amendment right to public carry.” Id. at 38, 142 S.Ct. 2111 n.9 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783). “Rather, it appears that these shall-issue regimes, which often require applicants to undergo a background check or pass a firearms safety course, are designed to ensure only that those bearing arms in the jurisdiction are, in fact, ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens.’ ” Id. (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783). And those regimes do so by applying “ ‘narrow, objective, and definite standards’ guiding licensing officials.” Id. (quoting Shuttlesworth v. Birmingham, 394 U.S. 147, 151, 89 S.Ct. 935, 22 L.Ed.2d 162 (1969)).
The Court also made clear that New York's proper-cause requirement did not resemble the laws of the “[t]hree States—Connecticut, Delaware, and Rhode Island—[that] have discretionary criteria but appear to operate like ‘shall issue’ jurisdictions.” Id. at 13, 142 S.Ct. 2111 n.1. For example, “[a]lthough Connecticut officials have discretion to deny a concealed-carry permit to anyone who is not a ‘suitable person,’ the ‘suitable person’ standard precludes permits only to those ‘individuals whose conduct has shown them to be lacking the essential character o[r] temperament necessary to be entrusted with a weapon.’ ” Id. (first quoting Conn. Gen. Stat. § 29-28(b) (2021); then quoting Dwyer v. Farrell, 193 Conn. 7, 475 A.2d 257, 260 (1984)). Likewise, the Court explained that, while “Rhode Island has a suitability requirement, ․ the Rhode Island Supreme Court has flatly denied that the ‘[d]emonstration of a proper showing of need’ is a component of that requirement.” Id. (quoting Gadomski v. Tavares, 113 A.3d 387, 392 (2015); citing R.I. Gen. Laws § 11-47-11).
The Supreme Court's simultaneous endorsement of Connecticut and Rhode Island's suitability regimes and criticism of state laws that give licensing officials “discretion to deny licenses based on a perceived lack of need or suitability,” id. at 13, 142 S.Ct. 2111, suggests that States cannot grant or deny licenses based on suitable need or purpose but may do so based on the applicant having a suitable character or temperament to handle a weapon.12
E. Rahimi
In Rahimi, the Supreme Court addressed the constitutionality of a federal statute, 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(8), which criminalizes possession of firearms by an individual who is subject to a domestic violence restraining order that either (i) rests on a finding that the defendant “ ‘represents a credible threat to the physical safety’ of his intimate partner or his or his partner's child,” or (ii) “explicitly prohibit[s]” the use or threat of physical force against those individuals. 144 S. Ct. at 1896 (quoting 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(8)(C)).
As in Bruen, the specific holding of Rahimi was narrow. Just as Bruen struck down a specific statute that required applicants to demonstrate a “special need” in seeking a permit to carry firearms, 597 U.S. at 11, 142 S.Ct. 2111, Rahimi upheld a particular statute that prohibited the carrying of firearms by persons who had been found by a court to pose a threat of physical harm to other persons, for the duration of time that a restraining order resulting from that finding was in place, 144 S. Ct. at 1896. Thus, the particular holdings of both cases concerned statutes quite different from the statutes at issue before us—neither concerned the type of licensing regime adopted by New York in the wake of Bruen, nor did they concern the restriction of firearms carriage in “sensitive locations.” Nevertheless, both cases are significant for the methodology that they adopt.
In Rahimi, the Court reiterated its statement in Heller that the right embodied in the Second Amendment is not “a right to keep and carry any weapons whatsoever in any manner whatsoever and for whatever purpose.” Id. at 1897 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783). Further, the Court expressly rejected the argument, advanced by some courts and commentators, that only regulations “identical to ones that could be found in 1791” are permitted by the Second Amendment. Id. at 1898. Rather, “the appropriate analysis involves considering whether the challenged regulation is consistent with the principles that underpin our regulatory tradition.” Id. (citing Bruen, 597 U.S. at 26–31, 142 S.Ct. 2111) (emphasis added). That analysis, consistent with Bruen’s pronouncement that present-day regulations need not “precisely match” historical precedents, id. (citing Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111), was absolutely necessary to the Rahimi holding, because, as the Court acknowledged and the sole dissenter emphasized, id. at 1933 (Thomas, J., dissenting), there was no close parallel in 1791 to statutes permitting restraining orders against domestic abusers, or forbidding firearms possession by those subject to such orders.
Despite the absence of a specific precedent directly analogous to the challenged statute, the Court found “ample evidence that the Second Amendment permits the disarmament of individuals who pose a credible threat to the physical safety of others.” Id. at 1898. Since § 922(g)(8) prohibits firearm possession by individuals who have been specifically determined to pose a threat to the safety of another person, it fell within that “regulatory tradition.” Id. at 1901.
The Court reached that conclusion primarily by analogy to two types of 18th-century weapons regulations that were “relevantly similar” but “by no means identical” to § 922(g)(8). Id. (quotation marks omitted). First, “[u]nder the surety laws, a magistrate could ‘oblige those persons, of whom there is probable ground to suspect of future misbehavior, to stipulate with and to give full assurance that such offense shall not happen, by finding pledges or securities,’ ” such as by posting a bond. Id. at 1899–900 (quoting 4 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 251 (10th ed. 1787) (hereinafter, “Blackstone”)) (alterations adopted). Second, the court looked to the “going armed laws,” which prohibited “riding or going armed, with dangerous or unusual weapons, [to] terrify[ ] the good people of the land.” Id. at 1901 (quoting 4 Blackstone 149) (alterations in original). Because “[s]uch conduct disrupted the public order and led almost necessarily to actual violence[,] ․ the law punished these acts with forfeiture of the arms and imprisonment.” Id. (quotation marks omitted and alterations adopted).
Neither of those sets of laws “precisely match[ed]” a criminal prohibition of possession of firearms by a particular class of person based on a prior civil imposition of a protective order. Id. at 1898. Nonetheless, the Court concluded that § 922(g)(8) is “analogous enough [to those laws] to pass constitutional muster,” as it comports “with the principles underlying the Second Amendment.” Id. (quoting Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111). Namely, both sets of laws “confirm what common sense suggests: When an individual poses a clear threat of physical violence to another, the threatening individual may be disarmed,” and § 922(g)(8) “fits neatly within th[at] tradition.” Id. at 1901.
Although the Court noted that the specific statute before it, like the surety laws (but unlike the “going armed” laws), disarmed the person subject to the protective order only for a delimited period and applied only to persons found by a court to pose a danger to a particular other person, the Court “[did] not suggest that the Second Amendment prohibits the enactment of laws banning the possession of guns by categories of persons thought by a legislature to present a special danger of misuse.” Id. (citing Heller, 554 U.S. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783). To the contrary, the Court again reiterated its prior statement in Heller that “many ․ prohibitions [on the possession of firearms, in the home], like those on the possession of firearms by ‘felons and the mentally ill,’ are ‘presumptively lawful.’ ” Id. at 1902 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 626, 627 n.26, 128 S.Ct. 2783).
Finally, the Court provided additional guidance to the lower courts as to the proper scope of the Second Amendment, albeit in a passage that was not necessary to the disposition of the case before it, which had already been resolved on the grounds that “dangerous” individuals may be temporarily disarmed. See id. at 1903. Namely, the Court “reject[ed] the Government's contention that [an individual] may be disarmed simply because he is not ‘responsible,’ ” noting that that term is “vague” and would lead to “unclear” results. Id. The Court further stated that the use of “responsib[ility]” as a guiding principle of the Second Amendment did not derive from its case law. Id. Although both Heller and Bruen used the term “to describe the class of ordinary citizens who undoubtedly enjoy the Second Amendment right,” those decisions “said nothing about the status of citizens who were not ‘responsible.’ ” Id. (citing Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783, and Bruen 597 U.S. at 70, 142 S.Ct. 2111).
F. History and Tradition
Bruen requires courts to engage in two analytical steps when assessing Second Amendment challenges: first, by interpreting the plain text of the Amendment as historically understood; and second, by determining whether the challenged law is consistent with this Nation's historical tradition of firearms regulation, as “that delimits the outer bounds of the right to keep and bear arms.” 597 U.S. at 19, 142 S.Ct. 2111. We focus here on the history-and-tradition prong.
As we understand it, history and tradition give content to the indeterminate and underdetermined text of the Second Amendment: “the right of the people to keep and bear Arms.” U.S. Const. amend. II. “As James Madison wrote, ‘a regular course of practice’ can ‘liquidate & settle the meaning of’ disputed or indeterminate ‘terms & phrases.’ ” Chiafalo v. Washington, 591 U.S. 578, 593, 140 S.Ct. 2316, 207 L.Ed.2d 761 (2020) (quoting Letter to S. Roane (Sept. 2, 1819), in 8 Writings of James Madison 450 (G. Hunt ed. 1908)). That is especially true of the Second Amendment: like the First Amendment, the Second Amendment codifies a pre-existing right, see Heller, 554 U.S. at 592, 603, 128 S.Ct. 2783; Bruen, 597 U.S. at 25, 34, 50, 142 S.Ct. 2111, and therefore can fairly be read to incorporate “traditional limitations” that existed at or around ratification, unless historical context suggests otherwise, cf. R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, 505 U.S. 377, 383, 112 S.Ct. 2538, 120 L.Ed.2d 305 (1992) (explaining that “ ‘the freedom of speech’ ․ does not include a freedom to disregard ․ traditional limitations”). Thus, while the literal text of the Second Amendment, like that of the First Amendment, contains no exception and therefore appears to be “unqualified,” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 17, 24, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Konigsberg v. State Bar of Cal., 366 U.S. 36, 50 n.10, 81 S.Ct. 997, 6 L.Ed.2d 105 (1961)), its indeterminate text is “not unlimited,” as the Supreme Court has repeatedly observed, id. at 21, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783). Accordingly, “reliance on history” and tradition “inform[s] the meaning of” the “pre-existing right” to keep and bear arms. Id. at 25, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (emphasis omitted).
That conclusion carries several implications. First, when used to interpret text, “not all history is created equal.” Id. at 34, 142 S.Ct. 2111. While ancient practices and postenactment history remain “critical tool[s] of constitutional interpretation,” Heller, 554 U.S. at 605, 128 S.Ct. 2783, they must be examined with some care because while history and tradition shed light on the meaning of the right to keep and bear arms, they do not create it. “Constitutional rights are enshrined with the scope they were understood to have when the people adopted them.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 34, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 634–35, 128 S.Ct. 2783). Thus, historical practices that long predate or postdate codification of the relevant constitutional provision may not have much bearing on the provision's scope if the practices were obsolete or anomalous. See id. For example, a one-off and short-lived territorial law, military decree, or local law, while no doubt relevant, will not carry the day if it contradicts the overwhelming weight of other evidence. See id. at 63 n.26, 67–68, 142 S.Ct. 2111. What matters is “our whole experience as a Nation.” Chiafalo, 591 U.S. at 593, 140 S.Ct. 2316 (quoting NLRB v. Noel Canning, 573 U.S. 513, 557, 134 S.Ct. 2550, 189 L.Ed.2d 538 (2014)).
Second, in examining history and tradition, a court must identify the “societal problem” that the challenged regulation seeks to address, Bruen, 597 U.S. at 26–27, 142 S.Ct. 2111, and then ask “whether the challenged regulation is consistent with the principles that underpin our regulatory tradition” for firearms, Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1898.13 “For instance, when a challenged regulation addresses a general societal problem that has persisted since the 18th century,” that regulation might more likely be unconstitutional if there is a “lack of a distinctly similar historical regulation addressing that problem,” if “earlier generations addressed the societal problem ․ through materially different means,” or if state courts struck down similar regulations addressing the same problem on “constitutional grounds.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 26–27, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Conversely, “where a governmental practice has been open, widespread, and unchallenged since the early days of the Republic, the practice should guide [a court's] interpretation of an ambiguous constitutional provision.” Id. at 36, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Noel Canning, 573 U.S. at 572, 134 S.Ct. 2550 (Scalia, J., concurring in the judgment)). And if courts during that period upheld similar governmental practices against similar constitutional challenges, that is strong evidence of constitutionality. Id. at 68, 142 S.Ct. 2111 & n.30.
Third, the absence of a distinctly similar historical regulation in the presented record, though undoubtedly relevant, can only prove so much. Legislatures past and present have not generally legislated to their constitutional limits. Reasoning from historical silence is thus risky; it is not necessarily the case that, if no positive legislation from a particular time or place is in the record, it must be because the legislators then or there deemed such a regulation inconsistent with the right to bear arms.14 There are many reasons why the historical record may not evidence statutory prohibitions on a given practice. For example, lawmakers are not often moved to forbid behavior that is governed by custom, universal practice, or private warning. No legislation is needed to forbid zoo patrons from entering the lion's enclosure; similarly, a town with only a single daycare facility that privately bans firearms from its premises has no need to pass a regulation prohibiting guns in daycare centers. Thus, “[t]he paucity of eighteenth century gun control laws might have reflected a lack of political demand rather than constitutional limitations.” Binderup v. Att'y Gen. United States of Am., 836 F.3d 336, 369 (3d Cir. 2016) (en banc) (Hardiman, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgments) (quoting Nelson Lund, The Second Amendment, Heller, and Originalist Jurisprudence, 56 UCLA L. Rev. 1343, 1354 (2009)). Stated differently, “novelty does not mean unconstitutionality.” Id. at 368. That is so even if the problems faced by past generations could be described, at a high level of generality, as similar to the problems we face today.
Fourth, courts must be particularly attuned to the reality that the issues we face today are different than those faced in medieval England, the Founding Era, the Antebellum Era, and Reconstruction. The Second Amendment does not consign us to “a law trapped in amber.” Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1897. Thus, the lack of a distinctly similar historical regulation, though (again) no doubt relevant, may not be reliably dispositive in Second Amendment challenges to laws addressing modern concerns. The Second Amendment “permits more than just those regulations identical to ones that could be found in 1791”; “[h]olding otherwise would be as mistaken as applying the protections of the right only to muskets and sabers.” Id. at 1897–98.
Such a lack of precedent was, to be sure, dispositive in Bruen. But that was due to the exceptional nature of New York's proper-cause requirement, which conditioned the exercise of a federal constitutional right on the right holder's reasons for exercising the right. As the Supreme Court explained, and as we repeated earlier, “[w]e know of no other constitutional right that an individual may exercise only after demonstrating to government officers some special need.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 70, 142 S.Ct. 2111. “[A] more nuanced approach” will often be necessary in cases challenging less exceptional regulations, including in cases concerning “new circumstances” or “modern regulations that were unimaginable at the founding,” such as regulations addressing “unprecedented societal concerns or dramatic technological changes.” Id. at 27–28, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
Fifth, under the more nuanced approach, the “historical inquiry that courts must conduct will often involve reasoning by analogy.” Id. at 28, 142 S.Ct. 2111. When reasoning by analogy, a court should ask whether the challenged regulation and the proposed historical analogue are “relevantly similar.” Id. at 29, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Cass Sunstein, On Analogical Reasoning, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 741, 773 (1993)). In making that determination, a court must identify an appropriate metric by which to compare the two laws. Id. Without “provid[ing] an exhaustive survey of the features that render regulations relevantly similar under the Second Amendment,” Bruen identified “at least two metrics: how and why the regulations burden a law-abiding citizen's right to armed self-defense.” Id. Thus, under the more nuanced approach, “whether modern and historical regulations impose a comparable burden on the right of armed self-defense and whether that burden is comparably justified are ‘central’ considerations when engaging in an analogical inquiry.” Id. (quoting McDonald, 561 U.S. at 767, 130 S.Ct. 3020).
Bruen emphasized that “analogical reasoning ․ is neither a regulatory straightjacket nor a regulatory blank check.” Id. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111. A court should not uphold modern laws simply because they remotely resemble historical outliers. Id. Conversely, a court should not search in vain for a “historical twin”; “a well-established and representative historical analogue” is sufficient. Id. Thus, “even if a modern-day regulation is not a dead ringer for historical precursors, it still may be analogous enough to pass constitutional muster.” Id. As an “example” of how modern regulations can be justified through analogical historical analysis, Bruen analogized regulations regarding schools and government buildings to historical “sensitive place” regulations regarding legislative assemblies, polling places, and courthouses:
Consider, for example, Heller’s discussion of “longstanding” “laws forbidding the carrying of firearms in sensitive places such as schools and government buildings.” 554 U.S. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783. Although the historical record yields relatively few 18th- and 19th-century “sensitive places” where weapons were altogether prohibited—e.g., legislative assemblies, polling places, and courthouses—we are also aware of no disputes regarding the lawfulness of such prohibitions. See D. Kopel & J. Greenlee, The “Sensitive Places” Doctrine, 13 Charleston L. Rev. 205, 229–236, 244–247 (2018); see also Brief for Independent Institute as Amicus Curiae 11–17. We therefore can assume it settled that these locations were “sensitive places” where arms carrying could be prohibited consistent with the Second Amendment. And courts can use analogies to those historical regulations of “sensitive places” to determine that modern regulations prohibiting the carry of firearms in new and analogous sensitive places are constitutionally permissible.
Id.
The Supreme Court's more recent decision in Rahimi further illustrates this point. The Court upheld a criminal prohibition of firearm possession by individuals with civil protection orders resulting from domestic violence against intimate partners. 144 S. Ct. at 1903. That prohibition was an extremely recent addition to the federal criminal code, having been enacted in 1994 under the Violent Crime Control and Law Enforcement Act of 1994. Pub. L. 103–322, tit. XI, § 110401, 108 Stat. 1796. Moreover, the underlying protective orders were themselves a relatively recent legal innovation. Neither the parties nor the Court were able to identify a “historical twin” from the 18th or 19th centuries. 144 S. Ct. at 1903 (quotation marks omitted). Nonetheless, the Court was untroubled by the absence of such a close analogue. Id. Instead, the Court noted that various laws from the 18th century and earlier authorized the prohibition of firearm possession by persons identified by legislatures and courts as dangerous to others. Id. at 1902–03. It concluded that § 922(g) was “sufficiently similar” to the historical tradition demonstrated by such laws so that the former was consistent with the Second Amendment. Id.
Sixth, just as the existence vel non of a distinctly similar historical regulation is not dispositive, it is likewise not dispositive whether comparable historical regulations exist in significant numbers. The Bruen Court's rejection of certain historical analogues due to the “miniscule territorial populations who would have lived under them” occurred in the exceptional context of a regulation that “ ‘contradic[ted] the overwhelming weight’ of other, more contemporaneous historical evidence.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 67–68, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 632, 128 S.Ct. 2783). Outside such exceptional contexts jurisdictions’ silence does not command the inference that legislators there deemed some other jurisdiction's regulation inconsistent with the right to bear arms. In a similar vein, while evidence that “some jurisdictions actually attempted to enact analogous regulations” that “were rejected on constitutional grounds ․ surely would provide some probative evidence of constitutionality,” id. at 27, 142 S.Ct. 2111, the lack of any “disputes regarding the lawfulness of such prohibitions” may lead to the inference that it was “settled” that states could prohibit or regulate arms in that manner “consistent with the Second Amendment,” id. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
Consider, for example, Bruen’s reference to legislative assemblies, polling places, and courthouses. In finding the constitutionality of laws restricting possession of firearms in those places supported by the historical record, Bruen cited a law review article and amicus curiae brief that cited a few laws existing around the time of the adoption of the Second Amendment. Id. Amicus curiae, for example, cited one law prohibiting arms at legislative assemblies, see 1647 Md. Laws 216; two laws prohibiting arms at polling places, see Del. Const. of 1776, art. 28; 1787 N.Y. Laws 345; and one law prohibiting arms in courthouses, see 1786 Va. Acts 33, ch.21. Although the law review article treated those laws as aberrational, see Kopel & Greenlee, supra, at 235–36, the Bruen Court examined those few prohibitions in context and explained that it was “aware of no disputes regarding the lawfulness of such prohibitions,” 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Thus, depending on the historical context, comparable historical laws need not proliferate to justify a modern prohibition.15
Seventh, as we noted above, the right to keep and bear arms is applicable to the States through the Fourteenth Amendment, see McDonald, 561 U.S. at 750, 130 S.Ct. 3020, which was adopted in 1868. Acknowledging as much, however, Bruen expressly declined to decide “whether courts should primarily rely on the prevailing understanding of an individual right when the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified in 1868 when defining its scope.” 597 U.S. at 37, 142 S.Ct. 2111. The Rahimi court similarly left that issue open. 144 S. Ct. at 1898 n.1.
Because the CCIA is a state law, the prevailing understanding of the right to bear arms in 1868 and 1791 are both focal points of our analysis.16 See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 34, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“Constitutional rights are enshrined with the scope they were understood to have when the people adopted them.” (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 634–35, 128 S.Ct. 2783)); McDonald, 561 U.S. at 778, 130 S.Ct. 3020 (plurality opinion) (“[I]t is clear that the Framers and ratifiers of the Fourteenth Amendment counted the right to keep and bear arms among those fundamental rights necessary to our system of ordered liberty.” (emphasis added)). The time periods in close proximity to 1791 and 1868 are also relevant to our analysis. True, the farther we depart from these key dates, the greater the chance we stray from the original meaning of the constitutional text. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 36–37, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Nevertheless, it is implausible that the public understanding of a fundamental liberty would arise at a historical moment, rather than over the preceding era.17 And it is implausible that such public understanding would promptly dissipate whenever that era gave way to another. In this way, sources from the time periods close around those dates “illuminat[e] the understanding of those steeped in the contemporary understanding of a constitutional provision.” Duncan v. Bonta, 83 F.4th 803, 819 (9th Cir. 2023) (Butamay, J., dissenting).
“McDonald confirms” that understanding. Ezell, 651 F.3d 684, 702 (7th Cir. 2011). As some scholars urged the Court to do,18 the McDonald plurality looked to evidence of the pre-Civil War and Reconstruction Eras to hold that right to keep and bear arms was a fundamental right fully applicable to the States. See 561 U.S. at 770–78, 130 S.Ct. 3020 (plurality opinion). In so holding, the plurality gave particular emphasis to how “the Framers and ratifiers of the Fourteenth Amendment counted the right to keep and bear arms among those fundamental rights necessary to our system of ordered liberty.” Id. at 778, 130 S.Ct. 3020 (emphasis added). It would be incongruous to deem the right to keep and bear arms fully applicable to the States by Reconstruction standards but then define its scope and limitations exclusively by 1791 standards.
We therefore agree with the decisions of our sister circuits—emphasizing “the understanding that prevailed when the States adopted the Fourteenth Amendment”—is, along with the understanding of that right held by the founders in 1791, a relevant consideration. Bondi, 61 F.4th at 1322; Wolford v. Lopez, 116 F.4th 959, 980 (9th Cir. 2024); see also Range v. Att'y Gen. United States of Am., 69 F.4th 96, 112 (3d Cir. 2023) (en banc) (Ambro, J., concurring) (observing that if the relevant period extends beyond the Founding era, “then Founding-era regulations remain instructive unless contradicted by something specific in the Reconstruction-era”), cert. granted, judgment vacated sub nom. Garland v. Range, ––– U.S. ––––, 144 S. Ct. 2706, ––– L.Ed.2d –––– (2024); Drummond v. Robinson Twp., 9 F.4th 217, 227 (3d Cir. 2021) (“[T]he question is if the Second and Fourteenth Amendments’ ratifiers approved regulations barring training with common weapons in areas where firearms practice was otherwise permitted.” (emphasis added)); Ezell, 651 F.3d at 702, 705–06 (explaining that a “wider historical lens” is required for a local—or state—regulation and considering evidence from both the Founding-era and Reconstruction).
We respectfully part ways with the Third Circuit, which held in Lara v. Commissioner Pennsylvania State Police, 91 F.4th 122, 134 (3d Cir. 2024), cert. granted, judgment vacated, 2024 WL 4486348, ––– U.S. ––––, ––– S.Ct. ––––, ––– L.Ed.2d –––– (U.S. Oct. 15, 2024), that “the Second Amendment should be understood according to its public meaning in 1791,” and not 1868. The Lara majority invoked Bruen's guidance that “individual rights enumerated in the Bill of Rights and made applicable against the States through the Fourteenth Amendment have the same scope as against the Federal Government.” Id. at 133 (quoting Bruen, 597 U.S. at 37, 142 S.Ct. 2111). The majority reasoned that if there is a conflict between the contemporaneous understandings of the right to bear arms at the time of ratification of the Second Amendment and that of the Fourteenth Amendment, “we must pick between the two timeframes.” Id. at 134, 142 S.Ct. 2111 n.14.
While we recognize that evidence nearest to 1791 can differ from that nearest to 1868, such discrepancy does not mean that the right to keep and bear arms was calcified in either 1791 or 1868. Rather, 1791 and 1868 are both fertile ground, and the adjacent and intervening periods are likewise places in the historical record to seek evidence of our national tradition of firearms regulation.
LICENSING REGIME
I. Overview
Plaintiffs’ first set of challenges address provisions of New York's law governing licensure of firearms. “New York maintains a general prohibition on the possession of ‘firearms’ absent a license.” Kachalsky, 701 F.3d at 85. Individuals holding a firearm license are exempt from most (but not all) of New York's criminal prohibitions on firearm possession. N.Y. Penal L. § 265.20(a)(3). “Section 400.00 of the Penal Law ‘is the exclusive statutory mechanism for the licensing of firearms in New York State.’ ” Kachalsky, 701 F.3d at 85 (quoting O'Connor v. Scarpino, 83 N.Y.2d 919, 920, 615 N.Y.S.2d 305, 638 N.E.2d 950 (1994)). Section 400.00 provides for many types of firearm licenses, see generally N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(2), but this case focuses on “concealed carry licenses,” which allow the holder to “have and carry [a pistol or revolver] concealed, without regard to employment or place of possession,” id. § 400.00(2)(f).
Before us are facial Second Amendment challenges to four components of New York's firearm licensing regime:
• N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(b) — To receive a firearm license, the applicant must be “of good moral character.” Following the enactment of the CCIA, “good moral character” means “having the essential character, temperament and judgment necessary to be entrusted with a weapon and to use it only in a manner that does not endanger oneself or others.” We refer to this provision as the “character requirement” or “character provision.” “Good moral character” appears to be a prerequisite for all types of firearm licenses, but since both the district court and the Plaintiffs discuss the character requirement only with respect to concealed carry licenses, and since the sole Plaintiff claiming he is injured by the licensing regime asserts a desire to obtain only a concealed carry license, we confine our discussion to that context.
• N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(o)(i) — An applicant for a concealed carry license must “submit to the licensing officer ․ names and contact information for the applicant's current spouse, [ ] domestic partner, [and] any other adults residing in the applicant's home, including any adult children of the applicant.” The applicant must further disclose “whether or not there are minors residing, full time or part time, in the applicant's home.” We refer to this provision as the “cohabitants requirement.”
• N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(o)(iv) — An applicant for a concealed carry license must “submit ․ a list of former and current social media accounts of the applicant from the past three years to confirm the information regarding the applicant[’]s character and conduct.” We refer to this provision as the “social media requirement.”
• N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(o)(v) — An applicant for a concealed carry license must “submit ․ such other information required by the licensing officer that is reasonably necessary and related to the review of the licensing application.” We refer to this provision as the “catch-all” requirement.
Plaintiffs argue that these requirements interfere with their right to carry a gun publicly and violate the Second Amendment because they lack a sufficient basis in the “Nation's historical tradition of firearm regulation.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 17, 142 S.Ct. 2111. The district court agreed and enjoined defendants from enforcing these four requirements.19 Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 349.
First, we conclude that at least one Plaintiff has presented a justiciable challenge to the licensing regime. The cohabitants, social media, and “catch-all” requirements have deterred Plaintiff Lawrence Sloane from obtaining a concealed carry license, which is a cognizable injury traceable to the enforcement of those provisions and redressable by an injunction. And given the close relationship between the disclosure requirements and the character requirement, Sloane's injury is attributable to the character provision itself and redressable by an injunction against enforcement. Although a plaintiff who challenges a rule that renders him ineligible to receive a license must first either seek a license or show that his application would be denied, a plaintiff (like Sloane) who challenges a component of the application process itself is not required to subject himself to that process in order to present a justiciable constitutional claim.
Second, on the merits, we affirm the district court's injunction in part and vacate it in part. We reject Sloane's challenges to the character, catch-all, and cohabitants requirements. The character requirement, we conclude, is not facially unconstitutional. A reasoned denial of a carry license to a person who, if armed, would pose a danger to themselves, others, or to the public is consistent with the well-recognized historical tradition of preventing dangerous individuals from possessing weapons. We do not foreclose as-applied challenges to particular character-based denials, but the provision is not invalid in all of its applications.
Nor does the bounded discretion afforded to licensing officers by the character provision render it invalid. On the contrary, Bruen explains that several licensing regimes with arguably discretionary criteria identical to New York's are consistent with its analysis. Similarly, although it is possible that a licensing officer could make an unconstitutional demand for information pursuant to the catch-all, we cannot conclude that there are no questions a licensing officer might constitutionally ask an applicant under that provision. Since the catch-all has a “plainly legitimate sweep,” we cannot strike it down on its face. Finally, the cohabitants requirement is consonant with the long tradition of considering an applicant's character and reputation when deciding whether to issue a firearm license.
But we affirm the preliminary injunction against enforcement of the social media requirement: although the review of public social media posts by a licensing officer poses no constitutional difficulties, requiring applicants to disclose even pseudonymous account names under which they post online imposes an impermissible infringement on Second Amendment rights that is unsupported by analogues in the historical record and moreover presents serious First Amendment concerns.
II. Standing
We must first consider our jurisdiction. E.g., Sinochem Int'l Co. v. Malaysia Int'l Shipping Corp., 549 U.S. 422, 430–31, 127 S.Ct. 1184, 167 L.Ed.2d 15 (2007). Article III courts have power to decide only “Cases” or “Controversies.” U.S. Const. art. III, § 2, cl. 1. “ ‘The doctrine of standing gives meaning to these constitutional limits,’ by requiring a plaintiff to ‘allege such a personal stake in the outcome of the controversy as to warrant his invocation of federal-court jurisdiction and to justify exercise of the court's remedial powers on his behalf.’ ” Knife Rights, Inc. v. Vance, 802 F.3d 377, 383 (2d Cir. 2015) (alteration adopted) (first quoting Susan B. Anthony List v. Driehaus, 573 U.S. 149, 157, 134 S.Ct. 2334, 189 L.Ed.2d 246 (2014); then quoting Warth v. Seldin, 422 U.S. 490, 498–99, 95 S.Ct. 2197, 45 L.Ed.2d 343 (1975)). “To establish Article III standing, a plaintiff must have ‘(1) suffered an injury in fact, (2) that is fairly traceable to the challenged conduct of the defendant, and (3) that is likely to be redressed by a favorable judicial decision.’ ” Silva v. Farrish, 47 F.4th 78, 86 (2d Cir. 2022) (quoting Spokeo, Inc. v. Robins, 578 U.S. 330, 338, 136 S.Ct. 1540, 194 L.Ed.2d 635 (2016)).
Lawrence Sloane is the sole Plaintiff in this case who claims standing to challenge New York's licensing regime. Sloane avers that he has long wanted to obtain a New York concealed carry license and “intended to apply for [his] carry license” after the Supreme Court decided Bruen. J.A. 144 (Sloane Decl. ¶¶ 3–4). But the CCIA caused him to reconsider because he is unwilling to “provide the government of New York with information about [his] family[ ] on the carry license application,” id. at 146 (Sloane Decl. ¶ 10); to submit “information about [his] associates, so some licensing official can interrogate them about [his] life,” id. at 147 (Sloane Decl. ¶ 16); and to “turn over [his] ‘social media’ ․ to the government[ ] as a condition of applying for a license,” lest he be forced to “self-censor ․ knowing that the state's prying anti-gun eye is looking over [his] shoulder,” id. at 145 (Sloane Decl. ¶¶ 8–9). He also objects to the required interview with the licensing officer “because there do not appear to be any limits on the questions [he can be] asked,” an objection we understand as relating also to the officer's ability to request supplemental information pursuant to the catch-all disclosure requirement. Id. at 147 (Sloane Decl. ¶ 17). Sloane does not have the option to omit this information, as incomplete applications “will not be processed.” Id. at 148 (Sloane Decl. ¶ 21 & n.2) (quoting Onondaga County Sheriff's website). But “[i]f these unconstitutional requirements were removed from the application,” Sloane declares, he “would immediately submit [an] application for a concealed carry license, something [he] greatly desire[s] to obtain and, but for the CCIA's unconstitutional demands, [he] would seek to obtain.” Id. at 151, 134 S.Ct. 2334 (Sloane Decl. ¶ 30).
Sloane has standing to challenge the disclosure requirements (which for standing purposes we assume to be unconstitutional) based on those averments. Sloane is deterred from seeking—and thereby prevented from obtaining—a concealed carry license; he is injured by the consequent inability to exercise his Second Amendment rights; that injury is traceable to the defendants’ enforcement of these provisions (their refusal to process applications omitting the required information); and the injury is redressable by the injunction that Sloane seeks, because he would apply if the requirements were stricken.
True, Sloane's injury stems from his own unwillingness to comply with the challenged requirements; but so long as the interest at stake is cognizable (as Sloane's interest in carrying a firearm surely is), a plaintiff suffers an injury-in-fact if the defendant's allegedly unlawful conduct impairs that interest, even if it does so by deterring the plaintiff due to his individual, but reasonable, sensibilities. In Friends of the Earth, Inc. v. Laidlaw Environmental Services (TOC), Inc., 528 U.S. 167, 120 S.Ct. 693, 145 L.Ed.2d 610 (2000), members of an environmental organization had standing to sue the operator of a wastewater treatment plant for discharging contaminants. Plaintiffs who wanted to visit the river for recreation had become unwilling to do so because of their own anxiety about the defendant's pollution. See id. at 181–83, 120 S.Ct. 693. The Court explained that the plaintiffs had a cognizable interest in their enjoyment and use of the river, and “Laidlaw's discharges ․ directly affected those affiants’ recreational, aesthetic, and economic interests” by way of their “reasonable concerns about the effects of those discharges.” Id. at 183–84, 120 S.Ct. 693. Since the plaintiffs had alleged that “they would use the [river] for recreation if Laidlaw were not discharging pollutants into it,” they had Article III standing. Id. at 184, 120 S.Ct. 693.
Sloane has standing with respect to the three disclosure requirements because defendants’ enforcement of the (allegedly unlawful) requirements impairs Sloane's interest in obtaining a license by deterring him from applying. However, the character requirement presents a slightly different question: rather than being a component of the application itself, the character provision determines who can receive a concealed carry license. And it is unclear at best whether Sloane is deterred by the character requirement itself, as opposed to the investigation it might prompt.
But the CCIA's character requirement is inextricable from its disclosure requirements. The State explains that the required disclosures are solely “intended to inform a licensing officer's assessment of good moral character”—they merely implement the character requirement. Nigrelli Br. at 29.20 Sloane's injury is thereby traceable to the character requirement itself, even if he is directly deterred only by the disclosure requirements. And an injunction against considering “good moral character” would redress Sloane's injury: if character ceased to determine the licensing decision, the State would have no reason for the invasive inquiries that deter Sloane from applying for a license. See J.A. 145–47 (Sloane Decl. ¶¶ 9, 10, 15). Thus, in these particular circumstances and on the record before us, we can decide his claims on the merits because we are satisfied that Sloane is suffering a cognizable injury that is traceable to the challenged provisions and redressable by the injunction he seeks.
Unsurprisingly, the State sees things differently. Relying on our decisions in United States v. Decastro, 682 F.3d 160 (2d Cir. 2012), and Libertarian Party of Erie County, the State contends that a litigant who wishes to challenge a licensing regime must either apply for a license and be denied or make a substantial showing that his application would be futile. But challenging a rule that limits eligibility for a license is different from challenging a component of the application process itself. This case is an example of the latter, while the Decastro rule governs only the former.
In Decastro, the criminal defendant challenged his conviction for unlawful transport of a firearm across state lines: New York's licensing regime was so restrictive, he argued, that the only way he could exercise his Second Amendment rights was to purchase a gun in another state and bring it into New York. See 682 F.3d at 163–64. We treated his claim as “tantamount to a challenge to [New York's licensing] scheme” on the theory that the New York regime was “constitutionally defective” because it barred too many individuals from gun ownership. Id. Given the nature of this claim, we concluded that he “lack[ed] standing to challenge the licensing laws of the state” because he had failed to show that he was one of those individuals rendered ineligible for a permit, i.e., that he had been or would have been denied a license under the allegedly-unconstitutional rules.21 Id. at 164; cf. id. at 163 (“ ‘[A] person to whom a statute may constitutionally be applied will not be heard to challenge that statute on the ground that it may conceivably be applied unconstitutionally to others.’ ” (quoting Parker v. Levy, 417 U.S. 733, 759, 94 S.Ct. 2547, 41 L.Ed.2d 439 (1974)). We applied Decastro to conceptually identical claims in Libertarian Party, in which the plaintiffs argued that New York had impermissibly restricted eligibility for firearm licenses. See 970 F.3d at 114–15. But since many of the plaintiffs had neither applied for licenses nor demonstrated futility, we dismissed their claims for lack of standing. Id. at 121–22.
Decastro governs only challenges to a licensing rule regarding eligibility. Bruen also exemplifies this sort of challenge: the plaintiffs asserted a desire (and right) to carry a gun publicly, sought a license to do so, and were denied based on an eligibility rule—the proper cause requirement—which they alleged was unconstitutionally restrictive. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 15–16, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Since the plaintiff's injury in such a case stems from his personal ineligibility for a license, the plaintiff must prove up that premise either by applying for a license or by making a substantial showing of futility. In this context, then, “futility” refers to the outcome of the contemplated application, i.e., whether the result is preordained. See Decastro, 682 F.3d at 164 (sufficiency of a futility showing is judged on whether plaintiff has shown that his application would have been denied); Bach v. Pataki, 408 F.3d 75, 82–83 (2d Cir. 2005) (application was futile where applicant “was statutorily ineligible for [the] carry license”); Image Carrier Corp. v. Beame, 567 F.2d 1197, 1201–02 (2d Cir. 1977) (bid for contract was futile “since it is obvious that [the potential bidder] could not have been awarded a contract”). The district court therefore erred in concluding that Sloane's application was futile because it would not have been processed in a timely manner. See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 260. Futility refers to the denial of an application; delays in receiving a decision do not render an application futile.
Sloane's challenge, however, is of a different type. Rather than challenge eligibility criteria, Sloane argues that a portion of the application process is unconstitutional. His injury flows from the application itself, not from his asserted ineligibility for a license. Indeed, he pleads the opposite: “Lawrence Sloane ․ is a law-abiding person ․ and is (aside from not having a license) eligible to possess and carry firearms in the state of New York.” J.A. 19 (Compl. ¶ 7). The State's reliance on Decastro is thus premised on its misapprehension of the nature of Sloane's claim. The State even asserts that “the license application ‘denial ․ is [the] distinct injury’ ” whenever a plaintiff challenges a licensing regime. 22 Nigrelli Br. at 26 (alterations in original) (quoting Parker v. District of Columbia, 478 F.3d 370, 376 (D.C. Cir. 2007)). But when the plaintiff challenges the application itself (or as here, a portion thereof), he is not required to first apply for and be refused a license. See Brokamp v. James, 66 F.4th 374, 387–89 (2d Cir. 2023) (no application or futility required when mental health counselor challenged licensing requirement as violation of First Amendment right to give counsel); Desiderio v. National Ass'n of Securities Dealers, Inc., 191 F.3d 198, 202 (2d Cir. 1999) (would-be securities dealers’ challenge to mandatory arbitration consent as condition to licensure).23
By eliding the distinction between challenges to eligibility rules and to the application process, the State in effect argues that the only way a plaintiff can challenge an application process is to do exactly what the plaintiff claims that he may not be required to do. Such a rule contravenes common sense. An applicant who challenges an application itself is not required to first comply with the objected-to component before bringing suit. Therefore, Sloane may challenge the disclosure requirements without first making the required disclosures.
III. Merits
Having assured ourselves of our jurisdiction, we consider whether the challenged portions of New York's licensing regime violate the Constitution.
A. The Character Requirement
To recapitulate, the character requirement states that “[n]o license shall be issued or renewed except for an applicant ․ of good moral character.” N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(b). Since 1913, New York has required concealed carry licensees to possess “good moral character,”24 but this phrase was left statutorily undefined until the CCIA added the following definition: “having the essential character, temperament and judgement necessary to be entrusted with a weapon and to use it only in a manner that does not endanger oneself or others.” Id.
Between them, Sloane and the district court put forward three reasons why the character requirement is unconstitutional. First, Sloane contends that the character requirement is, despite its century-long history, facially inconsistent with the history and tradition of firearm regulation. Second, the district court concluded that the discretion baked into the character provision is unsupported by history and tradition, and is therefore impermissible. Finally, Sloane argues that statements in Bruen categorically forbid states from conferring any discretion on licensing officers.
We reject all three arguments and vacate the district court's injunction against enforcement of the character requirement. First, the requirement is not facially invalid because it is not unconstitutional in all its applications. The CCIA's definition of “character” is a proxy for dangerousness: whether the applicant, if licensed to carry a firearm, is likely to pose a danger to himself, others, or public safety. And “[s]ince the founding, our Nation's firearm laws have included provisions preventing individuals who threaten physical harm to others from misusing firearms.” Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1896. We therefore cannot conclude that every denial on grounds of “good moral character” as defined by New York will violate the Second Amendment, though various avenues lie open for as-applied challenges.
Next, we disagree with the district court's conclusion that affording licensing officers a modicum of discretion to grant or deny a concealed carry permit is inconsistent with the Nation's tradition of firearm regulation. For as long as licensing has been used to regulate privately-owned firearms, issuance has been based on discretionary judgments by local officials. Licensing that includes discretion that is bounded by defined standards, we conclude, is part of this Nation's history and tradition of firearm regulation and therefore in compliance with the Second Amendment.
Finally, Bruen does not forbid discretion in licensing regimes—on the contrary, the Bruen Court specifically stated that its decision did not imperil the validity of more than a dozen licensing schemes that confer discretion materially identical to the CCIA. 597 U.S. at 38 n.9, 142 S.Ct. 2111. At most, the Court indicated that the practical operation of a licensing scheme is relevant to whether it is impermissibly discretionary. It was therefore error to strike down New York's scheme on a facial challenge.
1. Facial Second Amendment Challenge
At the outset, the State argues that the character requirement does not actually implicate the Second Amendment and therefore may be upheld without reference to historical analysis. Bruen instructs that history is relevant only if “the Second Amendment's plain text covers an individual's conduct,” 597 U.S. at 17, 142 S.Ct. 2111, and this threshold inquiry requires courts to consider three issues: whether the conduct at issue is protected, whether the weapon concerned is “in common use,” and whether the affected individuals are “ordinary, law-abiding, adult citizens” and thus “part of ‘the people’ whom the Second Amendment protects.” See id. at 31–32, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (resolving all three of these questions before proceeding to historical analysis). The State contends that, because the character requirement requires only that licensees can be entrusted to wield a gun responsibly, it does not infringe the rights of “law-abiding, responsible citizens” and so need not be assessed for consistency with history and tradition.
This potentially dispositive argument bears upon the scope of the Second Amendment right. The State reasons that the character provision impairs the ability to bear arms only of those individuals who do not have Second Amendment rights in the first place: the irresponsible. That is, at best, a controversial supposition. Though the Supreme Court has suggested that “law-abiding,” “responsible,” and/or “ordinary” individuals are protected by the Second Amendment,25 it is far from clear whether the negative of those adjectives describe individuals who stand outside the Second Amendment or instead those who may be disarmed consistent with that Amendment. See Kanter v. Barr, 919 F.3d 437, 452 (7th Cir. 2019) (Barrett, J., dissenting) (summarizing these two positions and explaining that “one uses history and tradition to identify the scope of the right, and the other uses that same body of evidence to identify the scope of the legislature's power to take it away”). Indeed, the Fifth Circuit, the Third Circuit en banc, and then-Judge Barrett in a Seventh Circuit dissent have advocated the latter view (contrary to the State's position here).26 See id. at 453 (Barrett, J., dissenting); Rahimi I, 61 F.4th at 451–53; Range, 69 F.4th at 101–03.
But we may resolve this appeal without opining on a tricky question with wide-ranging implications. The character requirement has not been enforced against a Plaintiff, nor has any Plaintiff alleged that he would be denied a license on character grounds—Sloane therefore brings only a facial challenge to the character provision. See N.Y. State Rifle & Pistol Ass'n, Inc. v. Cuomo, 804 F.3d 242, 265 (2d Cir. 2015) (“Because plaintiffs pursue this ‘pre-enforcement’ appeal before they have been charged with any violation of law, it constitutes a ‘facial,’ rather than ‘as-applied,’ challenge.”). And even assuming that the character requirement does impair Second Amendment rights,27 Sloane has failed to demonstrate that it is unconstitutional on its face.
“[C]lassifying a lawsuit as facial or as-applied affects the extent to which the invalidity of the challenged law must be demonstrated ․” Bucklew v. Precythe, 587 U.S. 119, 138, 139 S.Ct. 1112, 203 L.Ed.2d 521 (2019). To mount a successful facial challenge, the plaintiff “must ‘establish that no set of circumstances exists under which the [law] would be valid,’ or show that the law lacks ‘a plainly legitimate sweep.’ ” Ams. for Prosperity Found. v. Bonta, 594 U.S. 595, 615, 141 S.Ct. 2373, 210 L.Ed.2d 716 (2021) (alteration in original) (first quoting United States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739, 745, 107 S.Ct. 2095, 95 L.Ed.2d 697 (1987); then quoting Wash. State Grange v. Wash. State Republican Party, 552 U.S. 442, 449, 128 S.Ct. 1184, 170 L.Ed.2d 151 (2008)). In other words, “[a] facial challenge is really just a claim that the law or policy at issue is unconstitutional in all its applications.” Bucklew, 587 U.S. at 138, 139 S.Ct. 1112; accord Cmty. Hous. Improvement Program v. City of New York, 59 F.4th 540, 548 (2d Cir. 2023). For this reason, facial challenges are “the most difficult to mount successfully.” City of Los Angeles v. Patel, 576 U.S. 409, 415, 135 S.Ct. 2443, 192 L.Ed.2d 435 (2015) (alteration adopted and quotation omitted).
These general principles of constitutional adjudication apply in the context of Second Amendment litigation, as they do in cases involving other constitutional provisions. Rahimi specifically reiterated that point in addressing a facial Second Amendment challenge, noting that such a challenge is “the ‘most difficult challenge to mount successfully,’ because it requires [the challenger] to ‘establish that no set of circumstances exists under which the Act would be valid.’ ” 144 S. Ct. at 1898 (quoting Salerno, 481 U.S. at 745, 107 S.Ct. 2095). The Court further emphasized that, “to prevail, the Government need only demonstrate that [the challenged statute] is constitutional in some of its applications.” Id. (emphasis added).
There are applications of the character provision that would be constitutional. The Second Amendment does not preclude states from denying a concealed-carry license based on a reasoned determination that the applicant, if permitted to wield a lethal weapon, would pose a danger to himself, to others, or to public safety. There is widespread agreement among both courts of appeals and scholars that restrictions forbidding dangerous individuals from carrying guns comport with “this Nation's historical tradition of firearm regulation,” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 17, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Indeed, the Supreme Court has repeatedly admonished that the Second Amendment protects the rights of law-abiding and responsible citizens.28 It also has approved of “shall-issue” licensing regimes that deny firearms licenses to individuals who lack good moral character in the sense that they are not law-abiding and responsible and pose a danger to the community if licensed to carry firearms in public.29 The Court's statements reflect a recognition that such regulations are not inherently inconsistent with the Second Amendment or our historical traditions. Whether the relevant tradition is limited to dangerousness, or more broadly permits the disarmament of all law-breakers or “unvirtuous” individuals is the subject of considerable debate,30 but the use of dangerousness as a disqualifier does not appear controversial.31 However this tradition is characterized, the Supreme Court's approving references to “good moral character” licensing requirements, as imposed in states with requirements that define “good moral character” essentially as New York now defines it, demonstrate that such requirements are permissible.32
Such dangerousness is the core of New York's character requirement, as clarified in the CCIA. The gravamen of the “character” inquiry is whether the applicant can “be entrusted with a weapon and to use it only in a manner that does not endanger oneself or others.” N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(b) (emphasis added). The denial of a license to an individual deemed likely to pose such a danger (by, for instance, using a weapon unlawfully against another or by refusing to take safety precautions) is an application squarely within the provision's heartland. Such a denial would clearly fall within the historical tradition of preventing dangerous individuals from carrying guns. Since at least some possible applications of the character requirement would not violate the Constitution, it is not unconstitutional on its face.33
The district court effectively acknowledged as much, concluding that it would be constitutional to deny a license to “applicants who have been found, based on their past conduct, to be likely to use the weapon in a manner that would injure themselves or others (other than in self-defense).” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 305. The court nevertheless concluded that the provision was facially invalid because of the possibility of license denials in other situations that the court deemed unconstitutional. Id. That possibility cannot support a facial challenge. The denials the district court described as constitutional are likely (at least) applications of the character provision as enacted; the prospect that the scheme might also permit a licensing officer to deny a license unconstitutionally is insufficient to strike the provision down in all of its applications. See Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1903 (in addressing a facial challenge, courts must “consider the circumstances in which [the challenged statute] [i]s most likely to be constitutional,” rather than “focus[ ] on hypothetical scenarios where [the statute] might raise constitutional concerns”).
The district court's reasoning seems to rely in part on its view that Bruen “create[d]” an “exception” to the normal rules regarding facial and as-applied challenges, wherein it would “defy [the Bruen] standard for [a court] to find that such a law is inconsistent with history and tradition, just to watch it be saved by the one possible application that makes it constitutional.” See id. at 305. We do not agree. It would be highly unlikely that the Court would upend longstanding principles of constitutional litigation by mere implication. Indeed, as noted above, Rahimi expressly confirmed that those principles apply in the context of Second Amendment challenges. See 144 S. Ct. at 1898, 1903.
Bruen was a facial challenge and proceeded accordingly. But, unlike the character requirement here, the premise of the proper-cause rule at issue in Bruen (that “ordinary, law-abiding, adult citizens,” 597 U.S. at 31, 142 S.Ct. 2111, can be prohibited from carrying a gun if they lack a good reason to do so) was unsupported by history and thus violated the Second Amendment. How that rule was applied in particular cases was irrelevant given its facial constitutional flaw.
We recognize that “good moral character”—at least if untethered from the CCIA's limiting definition—may be seen as a spongy concept susceptible to abuse, but such abuses, should they become manifest, can still be corrected in court as they arise. A licensing officer who denies an application on character (or any other) grounds must provide “a written notice to the applicant setting forth the reasons for such denial,” N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(4-a). A notice that does not articulate the evidence underlying the character determination or that fails to connect that evidence to the applicant's untrustworthiness to carry a gun without endangering the safety of himself or others may well be deemed arbitrary and thus subject to vacatur under Article 78 of the New York Civil Practice Law and Rules, see N.Y. C.P.L.R. §§ 7801–06. Moreover, a rejected applicant can file an internal administrative appeal of his denial. See N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(4-a).34 And if those statutory remedies fail to correct any error, an as-applied challenge could be pursued in federal court.
Likewise, a licensing decision that uses “good moral character” as a smokescreen to deny licenses for impermissible reasons untethered to dangerousness, such as the applicant's lifestyle or political preferences, would violate the Constitution by relying on a ground for disarmament for which there is no historical basis.35 And we further agree with Sloane (and the district court) that it would violate the Second Amendment to deny a license because the applicant is willing to use a weapon in lawful self-defense (and thereby be said to “endanger ․ others”). See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 299, 303 (noting this problem). But that observation is insufficient to enjoin enforcement of the law. Contrary to the district court's view, see id. at 304 (faulting the character provision for “fail[ing] to expressly remind the licensing officer to make an exception for actions taken in self-defense” (emphasis omitted)), so long as the law has a “plainly legitimate sweep,” Bonta, 594 U.S. at 615, 141 S.Ct. 2373—as this one does—the law need not catalog and expressly forbid potential abuses.
Plaintiffs assume that licensing officers will act in bad faith, but facial challenges require the opposite assumption. Permissible outcomes are possible (and we think likely) under the statute. “Facial challenges are disfavored” because they “often rest on speculation,” “raise the risk of ‘premature interpretation of statutes on the basis of factually barebones records,’ ” and “threaten to short circuit the democratic process by preventing laws embodying the will of the people from being implemented in a manner consistent with the Constitution.” Wash. State Grange, 552 U.S. at 450–51, 128 S.Ct. 1184 (quoting Sabri v. United States, 541 U.S. 600, 609, 124 S.Ct. 1941, 158 L.Ed.2d 891 (2004)). These principles confirm that a facial injunction against the character provision is inappropriate at this stage.
2. Historical Challenge to Licensing Officer Discretion
The district court deemed the character requirement facially invalid for a further reason: that the statutorily bounded discretion baked into the provision is inconsistent with the history of firearm regulation in the United States and thus violates the Second Amendment. See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. at 301–02. We disagree as a matter of historical fact. For as long as American jurisdictions have issued concealed-carry-licenses, they have permitted certain individualized, discretionary determinations by decisionmakers.
It is important at the outset to be clear about the possible meanings of the term “discretion.” Professor Ronald Dworkin long ago distinguished between strong and weak senses of the term. He emphasized that discretion “does not exist except as an area left open by a surrounding belt of restriction. It is therefore a relative concept. It always makes sense to ask ‘Discretion under which standards?’ ” Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously 31 (1977). A statutory scheme that gave officials discretion in the strong sense, such that they could grant or deny licenses as they saw fit, would plainly not pass muster. But almost any regime that describes standards that must be applied to a wide variety of individual cases creates a certain bounded area of discretion, in a weaker sense, in determining whether those standards are met. As the Supreme Court recognized in Bruen, licensing statutes that require “good moral character,” defined in terms of a person's ability to carry weapons without creating danger to themselves or others based on whether they are law-abiding persons, are permissible, even if they inevitably rely on the judgment of the licensing authorities in determining whether that criterion has been met. As we explain below, moreover, statutes that grant that kind of limited discretion in applying defined criteria are consistent with our tradition of firearms regulation.
The State has identified firearm licensing schemes from the years immediately following ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment that authorized local officials to issue permits in their limited discretion without the kind of objective criteria the district court deemed necessary.36 There are a lot of them.37 Many schemes omit criteria altogether, requiring only “written permission from the mayor,”38 or a “special written permit from the Superior Court.”39 See, e.g., Helena, Mont., Ordinance No. 43: Concealed Weapons, § 1 (June 14, 1883), in The Charter and Ordinances of the City of Helena, Montana 103–04 (Alexander C. Botkin ed., 1887); Fresno, Cal., Ordinance No. 6, § 25 (Nov. 5, 1885), printed in The Fresno Weekly Republican, Nov. 7, 1885, at 3; Monterey, Cal., Ordinance No. 49: To Prohibit the Carrying of Concealed Weapons, § 1 (Jan. 5, 1892), printed in The Ordinances of the City of Monterey 112 (1913).
Other schemes placed limits on eligibility that embedded a certain amount of discretion. For instance, an influential scheme in California authorized “[t]he Police Commissioners [to] grant written permission to [certain] peaceable person[s] ․ to carry concealed deadly weapons for [their] own protection.” San Francisco, Cal., Order No. 1,226: Prohibiting the Carrying of Concealed Deadly Weapons § 1 (July 9, 1875), reprinted in San Francisco Municipal Reports 886 (1875); accord, e.g., Sacramento, Cal., Ordinance No. 84: Prohibiting the Carrying of Concealed Deadly Weapons, Apr. 24, 1876, reprinted in Charter and Ordinances of the City of Sacramento 173 (R.M. Clarken ed., 1896); Oakland, Cal., Ordinance No. 1141: An Ordinance to Prohibit the Carrying of Concealed Weapons, § 1 (May 15, 1890), reprinted in General Municipal Ordinances of the City of Oakland, Cal. (Fred L. Burton ed., 1895). Indeed, the United States Congress enacted a similar scheme in 1892. See An Act to Punish the Carrying or Selling of Deadly or Dangerous Weapons Within the District of Columbia, and for Other Purposes, 27 Stat. 116, 116–17, ch. 159 (1892).
The State draws special attention to the history of discretionary licensing regimes in New York. Decades before the state-wide Sullivan Act in 1911, localities from around New York were enacting permitting schemes that depended on individualized assessments by local officials. See, e.g., J.A. 441–42 (New York, N.Y., An Ordinance to Regulate the Carrying of Pistols in the City of New York, § 2 (Feb. 12, 1878), printed in Proceedings of the Board of Aldermen of the City of New York 612–16 (1878)) (“1878 New York Ordinance”) (“Any person ․ who has occasion to carry a pistol for his protection, may apply of the officer in command at the station-house of the precinct where he resides, and such officer, if satisfied that the applicant is a proper and law-abiding person, shall give said person a recommendation to the Superintendent of Police ․ who shall issue a permit to the said person allowing him to carry a pistol of any description.”); J.A. 475 (Brooklyn, N.Y., Ordinance to Regulate the Carrying of Pistols, §§ 2, 4 (Oct. 25, 1880), printed in Brooklyn Daily Eagle, Oct. 26, 1880) (“1880 Brooklyn Ordinance”) (similar); J.A. 482 (Elmira, N.Y., Official Notice (July 18, 1892), printed in Elmira Daily Gazette and Free Press, July 22, 1892) (similar); J.A. 478–79 (An Act to Revise the Charter of the City of Buffalo, 1891 N.Y. Laws 127, 176–77, ch. 105, § 209) (“The superintendent [of police] may, upon application in writing, setting forth under oath sufficient reasons, issue to any person a permit in writing to carry any pistol or pistols in the city. ․ No person ․ shall, in the city, carry concealed upon or about his person, any pistol or revolver ․ without having first obtained a permit, as hereinbefore provided.”).
These regimes were among the earliest concealed-carry-licensing schemes enacted in the Nation.40 For as long as licenses to carry concealed weapons have been issued in this country, the officials administering those systems have been tasked with making individualized assessments of each applicant. See also Clayton E. Cramer & David B. Kopel, Shall Issue: The New Wave of Concealed Handgun Permit Laws, 62 Tenn. L. Rev. 679, 681 (1995) (noting that the first permitting statutes “were broadly discretionary; while the law might specify certain minimum standards for obtaining a permit, the decision whether a permit should be issued was not regulated by express statutory standards”). Nor was discretionary licensing a transient measure: cities and states continued enacting such schemes into the early-twentieth century and beyond. See generally Charles Amicus Br. at 13–17 & App'x 2.41 Indeed, the record thus suggests that the kind of purely “objective” licensing scheme which the district court deemed required by history and tradition is in fact a historical outlier.42
The geographical breadth of licensing schemes that confer a measure of discretion likewise demonstrates their place in “our whole experience as a Nation,” Chiafalo, 591 U.S. at 593, 140 S.Ct. 2316 (quoting NLRB v. Noel Canning, 573 U.S. 513, 557, 134 S.Ct. 2550, 189 L.Ed.2d 538 (2014)); see supra Background § III.F. Cities from across the country, from San Francisco and Eureka to New York and Elmira, adopted similar discretionary permitting schemes. That widespread adoption by diverse and distant localities under varying circumstances suggests that these policies enjoyed broad popular support and were understood at the time to be consistent with the Second and Fourteenth Amendments. See Saul Cornell, The Right to Regulate Arms in the Era of the Fourteenth Amendment: The Emergence of Good Cause Permit Schemes in Post-Civil War America, 33 U.C. Davis. L. Rev. Online 65, 85 (2021).
Strikingly, moreover, these laws and ordinances did not merely exist—they appear to have existed without constitutional qualms or challenges. Plaintiffs cite, and we are aware of, no case in which laws of this type were found by courts to be inconsistent with federal or state constitutional provisions guaranteeing the right to bear arms before the Supreme Court's 21st century reinvigoration of the Second Amendment in Heller. Indeed, the record not only lacks any successful challenges to licensing schemes on such grounds, but also lacks any challenges at all.
It is unnecessary to consider whether licensing was a uniform practice in this period, nor whether officials’ limited discretion was unanimously allowed. Bruen instructs us to determine whether a given modern law is part of the Nation's tradition of firearm regulation, not the sum of it. That tradition is multiplicitous, consisting of many different attempts to balance individual freedom with public safety. And based on the evidence presented here, a branch of the tradition—dating to the years immediately following the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment—has employed laws that condition the ability to lawfully carry a concealed weapon on obtaining a permit based in part on an individualized assessment by a local official, frequently under lesser constraints than those in the CCIA or in the very similar statutes that the Bruen Court cited as acceptable. Given the frequency of such regulations, and the absence of successful constitutional challenges to them, we find it impossible to read out of our historical tradition the longstanding and established restriction of concealed carry licenses by those who present a danger to themselves or others, or who otherwise cannot be characterized as “law abiding, responsible citizens” simply because such regulations require some individualized application of a clearly delineated standard.
* * *
The district court discounted the evidence discussed above based on categorical rules it derived from Bruen. For instance, the district court relied on the “rule” that city ordinances are of lesser weight than state laws, Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 300, 306 n.81, and that the relevant laws are those that governed a certain percentage of the Nation's population, id. at 301.43 But Bruen merely warns against allowing “the bare existence of ․ localized restrictions” to “overcome the overwhelming evidence of an otherwise enduring American tradition.” 597 U.S. at 67, 142 S.Ct. 2111. It does not suggest that local laws are not persuasive in illuminating part of the Nation's tradition of firearm regulation. Similarly, the number of people subject to a given law is only one clue to whether said law may have been an outlier unable to refute a contrary tradition. See id. at 67–70, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
The district court also seemed to draw strong and specific inferences from historical silence, reasoning that, if the submitted record lacks legislation from a particular place, it must be because the legislators there deemed such a regulation inconsistent with the right to bear arms. That inference is not commanded by Bruen, nor is it sound. There are many reasons why the historical record may not reflect statutory prohibitions on a given practice. See supra Background § III.F; see also Binderup, 836 F.3d at 369 (Hardiman, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgments) (“The paucity of eighteenth century gun control laws might have reflected a lack of political demand rather than constitutional limitations.” (quoting Nelson Lund, The Second Amendment, Heller, and Originalist Jurisprudence, 56 UCLA L. Rev. 1343, 1354 (2009))). Moreover, our national tradition of firearms regulation has taken a multiplicity of forms, and a jurisdiction's use of another type of regulation may have obviated the need to enact a regulation analogous to the contemporary one at issue. For example, the city of Oakland operated a permitting system that restricted armed carriage, under which only seventy Oakland residents, out of a population of around 48,000, held a license in 1889. Carry Arms: Those Who Have Permits to Carry Concealed Weapons, Oakland Tribune (Cal.), July 20, 1889, at 1; Oakland Census Data for 1860–1940, Bay Area Census, http://www.bayareacensus.ca.gov/cities/Oakland40.htm [https://perma.cc/JJM2-3W3T]. Given the relatively small population that was licensed to be armed within the city's limits, Oakland's legislators likely would not have seen the need to also designate certain locations as sensitive places where armed carriage was absolutely prohibited. Bruen calls on courts to undertake an inquiry that sounds fundamentally in history rather than law: a court must ask itself what people of the past thought (or even assumed) about the right to bear arms and the regulations that comport with that right. And the Supreme Court understood that such historical analysis is marked by skepticism and nuance, rather than authority and precept. “[H]istorical analysis can be difficult; it sometimes requires resolving threshold questions, and making nuanced judgments about which evidence to consult and how to interpret it.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 25, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting McDonald, 561 U.S. at 803–804, 130 S.Ct. 3020 (Scalia, J., concurring)). It proceeded accordingly, declining to establish ironclad rules and instead noting considerations which would be “relevant evidence,” id. at 26, 142 S.Ct. 2111, or “could be evidence,” id., or “may not illuminate the scope of the right if” certain conditions are present, id. at 34, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
With that perspective, we are not troubled that many licensing schemes originated in the cities of the post-Civil War period. Licensing was the result of changes in American society in the nineteenth century, including urbanization and concomitant shifts in norms of governance. The post-Civil War world was transformed by rapid urbanization.44 And city people have long had a different relationship with guns than their rural neighbors, a relationship generally marked by greater concern about interpersonal violence. See Joseph Blocher, Firearm Localism, 123 Yale L. J. 82, 98–103, 112–21 (2013).
That was true in the Reconstruction era as well: New York City's 1878 concealed-carry ordinance made explicit the connection between the new urban environment and the bearing of arms as a potential problem; it warned that the disorderly and the intoxicated were going about carrying pistols, “insult[ing] respectable citizens, and draw[ing] a pistol on any and every occasion, while the better and law-abiding class try to obey the laws and protect themselves with nothing but nature's weapons.” J.A. 443; see also J.A. 440 (New York, N.Y., An Ordinance to Regulate the Carrying of Pistols in the City of New York, committee report) (“As to the necessity for the passage of the ordinance there can be no question. The reckless use of fire-arms by the dangerous classes in this city is proverbial, and this measure of repression seems to be necessary.”). The problem was made more serious by the increased lethality of firearms in the latter decades of the nineteenth century, see Profs.’ Amicus Br. at 19 (“[T]echnological advances spurred by the Civil War made guns more lethal and available.”): one military historian has estimated that firearms became ten times more lethal over the course of the nineteenth century, Trevor Nevitt Dupuy, The Evolution of Weapons and Warfare 92, 286–89 (1984).45
Accompanying the nineteenth-century explosive growth of cities was the development of governance institutions that were more tightly organized, specialized, and bureaucratic than those required by the towns of the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. “The transformation of the state is one of the most prominent themes of nineteenth-century American history,” and “[f]or the most part, it is a story of the expansion and increasing complexity of government and of the professionalization and decreasing popular character of politics.”46 It is no coincidence that true police forces come into being in this period, first in London, and then in Boston, New York, and Philadelphia in the 1830s.47
These new institutions and ideas shaped the response to increasingly lethal guns in increasingly populous cities and naturally led to a greater resort to legislation and regulation.48 Police-administered licensing schemes evinced a degree of administrative sophistication typical of the late-nineteenth century cities but unusual in the Founding Era. Cf. J.A. 440–41 (1878 New York Ordinance); J.A. 475 (1880 Brooklyn Ordinance). More generally, the growth of permitting schemes—as opposed to prohibitory laws enforced in the courts 49 —reflected the developing philosophy of proactive local government.50 In sum, “[o]ver the course of the nineteenth century, as America modernized and urbanized, professional police forces, police courts, and administrative agencies took over the job of maintaining public order from justice[s] of the peace. The new permit-based scheme emerged in the context of these larger changes in criminal justice.”51
In context, it makes sense that licensing regimes were instituted by cities rather than states, and that such schemes were not enacted until after the Civil War. We therefore see nothing in either the timing or urban origins of limited discretionary licensing regimes to justify discounting this tradition of American firearm regulation, which can be documented in the aftermath of the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment.
For the reasons above, we disagree with the district court's conclusion that licensing regimes that afford a modicum of discretion to issuing officers are not part of the Nation's tradition of firearm regulation and that the character provision thus violates the Second Amendment. We need not determine at what point a regime grants so much untethered discretion to licensing authorities as to be unconstitutional on its face; it is sufficient to conclude, as we do in the following section, that the CCIA's definition of ‘good moral character’ in terms of public safety, drawn from statutes that Bruen treats as likely constitutional, does not approach that point.
3. Bruen-Based Challenge to Licensing-Officer Discretion
Plaintiffs also attack the discretionary aspect of the character requirement on a different basis. They assert that Bruen announced a freestanding rule of constitutional law that requires states to determine eligibility for a gun license using only a checklist that wholly precludes individualized judgments. This claim is based on an overreading of one footnote in Bruen:
To be clear, nothing in our analysis should be interpreted to suggest the unconstitutionality of the 43 States’ “shall-issue” licensing regimes, under which a general desire for self-defense is sufficient to obtain a permit. Because these licensing regimes do not require applicants to show an atypical need for armed self-defense, they do not necessarily prevent law-abiding, responsible citizens from exercising their Second Amendment right to public carry. Rather, it appears that these shall-issue regimes ․ are designed to ensure only that those bearing arms in the jurisdiction are, in fact, law-abiding, responsible citizens. And they likewise appear to contain only narrow, objective, and definite standards guiding licensing officials rather than requiring the appraisal of facts, the exercise of judgment, and the formation of an opinion—features that typify proper-cause standards like New York's.
597 U.S. at 38 n.9, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (emphasis added; alterations adopted; quotation marks, and internal citations omitted).
Plaintiffs’ rule precluding all discretion cannot be squared with Bruen’s discussion of “shall-issue” regimes, even if one thought that the Court would announce a sweeping prohibition of discretion in a single sentence of a footnote designed to clarify the limited scope of its decision. Of the forty-three licensing regimes that Bruen described as consistent with its analysis, more than a dozen confer some measure of discretion on licensing officers, with many using terms that are nearly identical to New York's character provision. If “nothing in [Bruen] should be interpreted to suggest the unconstitutionality of” those licensing schemes, 597 U.S. at 38 n.9, 142 S.Ct. 2111, then Bruen did not totally foreclose discretion and does not require invalidation of New York's character requirement.
Earlier in Bruen, the Court explained that three states whose licensing regimes use “discretionary criteria”—Connecticut, Delaware, and Rhode Island—are nonetheless “shall-issue” jurisdictions (and thus, per footnote 9, consistent with Bruen).52 Connecticut licensing officers have “discretion to deny a concealed-carry permit to anyone who is not a ‘suitable person,’ ” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 13 n.1, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Conn. Gen. Stat. § 29-28(b) (2021)), but because Connecticut courts have supplied a narrowing gloss on that broad standard, Connecticut nonetheless qualified as a “shall-issue” state. Id. Connecticut's gloss on the suitability standard is nearly identical to the CCIA's definition of “good moral character,” excluding only those “individuals whose conduct has shown them to be lacking the essential character o[r] temperament necessary to be entrusted with a weapon.” Id. (quoting Dwyer, 475 A.2d at 260).
Bruen also classifies Delaware as a shall-issue jurisdiction notwithstanding its inherently discretionary “good moral character” provision, Bruen, 597 U.S. at 13 n.1, 142 S.Ct. 2111, which (like New York) requires that the applicant be “of ․ good moral character.” Del. Code Ann. tit. 11, § 1441(a) (2022); see also id. § 1441(a)(2) (requiring five character references attesting to the applicant's “sobriety and good moral character” and “good reputation for peace and good order in the community”). Finally, the Court explained that, though Rhode Island (like Connecticut) requires that an applicant be “a suitable person to be so licensed,” R.I. Gen. Laws § 11-47-11(a) (2002), its regime is “shall-issue” because (again like Connecticut) “suitability” does not require “[d]emonstration of a proper showing of need.’ ” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 13 n.1, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting Gadomski, 113 A.3d at 392).
Furthermore, without specific discussion, Bruen categorized as “shall-issue” jurisdictions at least twelve other licensing schemes that call for discretionary judgments, such as whether the applicant “causes justifiable concern for public safety,” Ala. Code § 13A-11-75(c)(11) (2021); “is likely to use a weapon unlawfully,” Iowa Code Ann. § 724.8(3) (West 2011); “likely ․ will present a danger to self or others if the applicant receives a permit,” Colo. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 18-12-203(2) (West 2023), etc.53 Similarly, many Bruen-compliant states forbid issuing a concealed carry license to individuals who, for example, “chronically or habitually abuse a controlled substance to the extent that his or her normal faculties are impaired,” Ark. Code Ann. § 5-73-309(7)(A) (2021); “suffer from a physical or mental infirmity that prevents the safe handling of a handgun,” N.C. Gen. Stat. Ann. § 14-415.12(a)(3) (West 2022); or exhibit a “condition relating to or indicating mental instability or an unsound mind,” Okla. Stat. Ann. tit. 21, § 1290.10(6) (West 2019). These are plainly determinations that “requir[e] the appraisal of facts, the exercise of judgment, and the formation of an opinion,” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 38 n.9, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quotation marks omitted).54
The same modicum of discretion as New York's character requirement is embedded in the licensing schemes discussed above. Indeed, Delaware uses the very phrase “good moral character,” and the CCIA's definition of that term matches Connecticut law nearly verbatim. Yet Bruen expressly denominated those states (not to mention the dozen others that call for discretionary judgments) as “shall-issue jurisdictions.” It therefore cannot be that Bruen even “suggest[s]”—let alone holds—that a licensing regime which confers some limited degree of discretion is facially invalid.55
Footnote 9 is better read as addressing laws that combine discretion with a special-need requirement. That combination—present in the invalid proper-cause regime but absent in the “shall-issue” regimes—separates unconstitutional from permissible licensing regimes. Bruen intimated as much in footnote 1: Rhode Island's discretionary scheme was “shall-issue” solely because “[d]emonstration of a proper showing of need” was not required. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 13 n.1, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (internal quotation omitted). Similarly, the Court described “shall-issue” regimes in the first sentence of footnote 9 as those “under which ‘a general desire for self-defense is sufficient to obtain a [permit].’ ” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 38 n.9, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (alteration adopted) (quoting Drake v. Filko, 724 F.3d 426, 442 (3d Cir. 2013) (Hardiman, J., dissenting)).56 And footnote 9 is appended to a sentence which faults New York's prior regime only for “limiting public carry only to those law-abiding citizens who demonstrate a special need for self-defense.” Id. at 38, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
At the very least, Bruen teaches that mere use of a “good moral character” requirement does not justify facial invalidation. Bruen gave great weight to state court interpretations of the Connecticut and Rhode Island standards, which indicated that the statutes, in practice, operated as “shall-issue” regimes. Whether such a scheme is impermissibly discretionary cannot be decided before it has been implemented and brought before state courts. Time may disclose whether New York's regime under the CCIA will “operate like a ‘shall-issue’ jurisdiction,” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 13 n.1, 142 S.Ct. 2111, or whether it will be narrowed in salient ways by the New York courts. Accordingly, facial invalidation is not appropriate. See Wash. State Grange, 552 U.S. at 450, 128 S.Ct. 1184 (warning against invalidating a law before “the State has had [an] opportunity to implement [it] and its courts have had no occasion to construe the law in the context of actual disputes ․ or to accord the law a limiting construction”).
Finally, Rahimi helps to explain Bruen’s endorsement of the constitutionality of “shall-issue” licensing regimes. As noted above, see supra note 40, licensing schemes as such developed after the Civil War, and thus could be argued to lack precedent at the time of the adoption of the Second Amendment. However, as we have also explained above, we regard evidence of the tradition of firearms regulation from around the time that the Fourteenth Amendment made the protection of the right to bear arms binding on the States as likewise significant. But even if we do not, Rahimi strongly suggests that what matters in the search for historical antecedents of modern firearms regulations is the substance of the regulation, rather than the form.
Rahimi held that the criminal law there at issue is consistent with the Second Amendment because around the time of the adoption of the Bill of Rights, well-established legal regulations governing firearms constrained the possession of firearms by such devices as (i) the “surety laws,” which gave magistrates the power to condition the possession of weapons by persons “suspected of future misbehavior” on the posting of a bond, 144 S. Ct. at 1899–900; and (ii) “going armed” laws, which criminally punished those who went about “with dangerous or unusual weapons, [to] terrify[ ] the good people of the land” by, among other sanctions, “forfeiture of the arms,” id. at 1901 (quoting 4 Blackstone 149) (alterations in original).
Those statutes did not utilize anything like the modern civil protective order that triggered the prohibition of 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(8) that was upheld in Rahimi. The surety laws allowed magistrates to restrain firearms possession by individuals who presented a risk of misusing them and who were unable to post a bond; the “going armed” laws used the device of forfeiture to disarm those convicted of certain criminal behavior. But those 18th-century regimes signaled the validity of the modern statute because they shared a critical substantive characteristic: they all used their differing procedural mechanisms to disarm those who were determined to be dangerous.57
The pre-modern surety laws, like the modern shall-issue licensing regimes (approved in Bruen) on which New York's CCIA was modeled, aimed to deny firearms to those for whom there is “probable ground to suspect of future misbehavior,” id. at 1899 (quoting 4 Blackstone 251), and the “going armed” laws similarly disarmed those with a past record of such dangerous misuse of weapons. Moreover, in the former case, the magistrates who administered the law had considerable discretion—in Dworkin's weaker sense of the word—to apply a broad general standard of future risk in order to deny to certain persons a right otherwise attaching to law-abiding persons.
Though the form of the licensing statute is different, its substance is analogous. The New York statute mandates the issuance of a license to anyone except those found to present a danger to the community. That standard requires the exercise of judgment by the licensing authorities (subject to administrative appeals and judicial review) that is no less precise than the “probable ground to suspect ․ future misbehavior” standard of the surety laws. Id. at 1899.
In sum, Bruen does not require that New York's character requirement be struck down by virtue of the limited discretion it affords to licensing officers. Given the patent incompatibility between Plaintiffs’ proffered reading of footnote 9 and the remainder of the Court's opinion, especially in light of Rahimi's reliance on the surety laws, we are confident that the Court did not establish a new rule forbidding all discretionary judgments in firearm licensing.
* * *
For the foregoing reasons, we VACATE the district court's preliminary injunction: licensing officers across New York may consider whether an applicant for a firearm license can be trusted to use that gun in a responsible, safe way. Licensing officers nevertheless have a statutory duty to make “character” determinations only with respect to an applicant's potential dangerousness, and a denial on that ground requires a written, reasoned notice of denial supported by evidence. Where necessary, both state and federal courts are empowered to enforce those statutory requirements and consider as-applied constitutional challenges, thereby ensuring that individuals are not prevented from carrying a gun on the basis of flimsy imputations, unsupported subjective intuitions, or hunches about the applicant's character. But there is currently no reason to doubt that licensing officers across New York will approach their task with diligence and a respect for the relevant constitutional interests.
B. The Catch-All
We VACATE the district court's injunction against the catch-all disclosure provision for the same reason: it is not facially unconstitutional. Though we (along with Plaintiffs and the district court) can think of situations in which the catch-all could be abused, there are plenty of possible applications that would be permissible.
Section 400.00(1)(o)(v) provides that “the applicant ․ shall, in addition to any other information or forms required by the license application[,] submit ․ such other information required by the licensing officer that is reasonably necessary and related to the review of the licensing application.” Sloane does not challenge a particular request made pursuant to this provision—none has been made. Instead, he argues that the authority to seek supplemental information is unconstitutional on its face because every application of the catch-all provision —i.e., any request a licensing officer could make—would be an unconstitutional burden on the right to bear arms. See, e.g., Bucklew, 587 U.S. at 138, 139 S.Ct. 1112 (“A facial challenge is really just a claim that the law or policy at issue is unconstitutional in all its applications.”).
However, as the district court recognized in a previous opinion in this litigation, it surely does not violate the Constitution for a licensing officer to request “only very minor follow-up information from an applicant (such as identifying information).” Antonyuk v. Hochul, 635 F. Supp. 3d 111, 137 (N.D.N.Y. 2022). There seems to be statutory authority in subparagraph (1)(o)(v) for licensing authorities to request the kind of information that one would find required by any government form, such as a driver's license number, social security number, or previous name. See N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(3) (mandating only that the license application state the applicant's name, date of birth, residence, occupation, and citizenship status). The catch-all therefore has a “plainly legitimate sweep.”
The district court struck down this provision (as it did the character requirement) as providing licensing officials with “unbridled discretion.” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 312. But neither the history of licensing regimes nor Bruen itself supports the conclusion that the conferral of some discretion to a licensing officer to request reasonable supplementary information is unconstitutional. Given that allowing discretionary denials of a license is part of the Nation's tradition of firearm regulation, there can be no constitutional problem with conferring the lesser discretion to ask for reasonable supplementary information.
Federal courts generally should be wary about granting facial challenges, which deny the opportunity for agency officials and state courts to interpret, apply, or limit state laws. As the Supreme Court has instructed, “[i]n determining whether a law is facially invalid, we must be careful not to go beyond the statute's facial requirements and speculate about hypothetical or imaginary cases. The State has had no opportunity to implement [the law], and its courts have had no occasion to construe the law in the context of actual disputes ․, or to accord the law a limiting construction ․” Wash. State Grange, 552 U.S. at 449–50, 128 S.Ct. 1184 (internal quotation marks and citations omitted).
As-applied challenges to particular requests made pursuant to the catch-all provision remain viable. There surely exist some possible requests which would unconstitutionally burden the right to bear arms: the reader can no doubt conceive of apt hypotheticals. But administrative and state and federal judicial remedies will be available to an applicant who is denied a license for declining to comply with a supplementary request. A court properly presented with a Second Amendment challenge to such a request will be able to assess whether the information requested is sufficiently analogous to historical restrictions on bearing arms. In addition, a disappointed applicant may argue that the licensing officer's request was not “reasonably necessary and related to the review of the licensing application,” and do so either in an administrative appeal or in an Article 78 proceeding.
But no such request for supplementary information is before us: Sloane chose instead to challenge the law on its face. And for the reasons stated above, a challenge so framed fails.
C. The Cohabitant Requirement
N.Y. Penal Law § 400.00(1)(o)(i) requires that an applicant (i) identify and provide contact information for their current spouse or domestic partner and any adult cohabitants, and (ii) disclose whether minors reside in the applicant's home. This provision is intended to “facilitate inquiries to the applicant's close associates for information relevant to the good-moral-character evaluation and assist in identifying red flags that may cast doubt on the applicant's ability to use firearms safely.” Nigrelli Br. at 40. Plaintiffs argue—and the district court held—that this requirement is unconstitutional on its face. We disagree and vacate the district court's injunction as to that provision.
The district court itself recognized the existence of a “sufficiently established and representative ․ tradition of firearm regulation based on reputation (for example, by a reasonable number of character references).” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 306. It accordingly upheld New York's requirement that applicants provide “four character references who can attest to the applicant's good moral character ․” N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(o)(ii); see Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 305–07. Plaintiffs do not challenge either conclusion here. In our view, disclosure of one's cohabitants (in part for the purpose of identifying references regarding the applicant's trustworthiness) is tantamount to the character-reference provision upheld by the district court. If the character-reference requirement is consistent with a historical tradition of firearm regulation, how can the cohabitant provision's requirement of a limited number of additional character references be inconsistent with that tradition?58
More generally, we have already explained that it is constitutional for a state to make licensing decisions by reference to an applicant's “good moral character,” at least where that “character” is defined in terms of dangerousness. It must therefore be constitutional for the licensing authority to investigate the applicant's character, and no one argues that a licensing officer may not inquire into the applicant's trustworthiness beyond the challenged disclosures. It follows that the State can also require modest disclosures of information that are relevant to that investigation and that will make the (permissible) assessment of dangerousness more efficient and more accurate.
This provision serves that end. In addition to providing an alternate means by which the licensing officer can learn of potential character references, the cohabitants themselves can inform the dangerousness inquiry. An assessment of an applicant's “good moral character” requires an evaluation of the whole individual. The identity and characteristics of an applicant's cohabitants are obviously relevant to the dangerousness of the applicant in situ. For instance, if an applicant living with multiple young children was unwilling or unable to secure firearms from meddling, surely a licensing officer could conclude that the applicant cannot “be entrusted with a weapon and to use it only in a manner that does not endanger [him]self or others,” N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(b).
Of course, conditioning a firearm license on disclosures that are burdensome and historically unprecedented can still violate the Second Amendment—we strike down one such disclosure obligation in the next section—but we conclude that the cohabitant requirement is not within that category. Instead, requiring disclosure of information regarding cohabitants imposes a similar burden as requesting supplemental identifying information, a disclosure that we (and the district court) have already recognized is constitutional. See supra Licensing Regime § III.B; Antonyuk, 635 F. Supp. 3d at 137. Put most simply, disclosing cohabitants is within the category of disclosures reasonably included in the kind of background check that has long been permissible.
Concluding otherwise, the district court reasoned that the disclosure is a burden “imposed solely for the licensing officers’ convenience” because the requested information is theoretically already in the State's possession in the form of “marriage licenses, children's birth certificates, guardianship forms, school forms, adoption paperwork, applications for driver's license or passport, and U.S. census forms.” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 307. At the outset, we have our doubts that the relevant agencies would willingly hand over adoption records, census forms, or school paperwork to licensing officers without objection. That aside, we draw the opposite conclusion from the fact that the State will usually already possess the requested information due to the disclosure requirements of its various other agencies: that there is only a minimal privacy interest in the identity of one's cohabitants. Disclosing that information again in another context is that much less burdensome. Unlike the social media provision discussed below, the cohabitants requirement does not demand information with constitutional implications or which the applicant has any special interest in concealing.
Moreover, the “convenience” of licensing officers, properly understood, is a legitimate consideration that, at least in this context, furthers the relevant constitutional values. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 38 n.9, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (suggesting that “lengthy wait times in processing license applications” may “deny ordinary citizens their right to public carry”). Background investigations should be quick and efficient, and should not require licensing officers to engage in burdensome cross-checks with other government records to learn relevant information that would result in unnecessary delays and backlogs in processing applications, especially where that information is routinely disclosed to the government in other contexts and is readily available to the applicant.
For these reasons, we conclude that Plaintiffs are not likely to succeed in their challenge to the cohabitants requirements and VACATE the district court's preliminary injunction against enforcing that provision.
D. The Social Media Requirement
Under N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(o)(iv), an applicant for a concealed carry license must “submit ․ a list of former and current social media accounts of the applicant from the past three years to confirm the information regarding the applicant[’]s character and conduct.” The district court rejected the State's proffered analogues, found “the burdensomeness of this modern regulation to be unreasonably disproportionate to the burdensomeness of any historical analogues,” and preliminarily enjoined enforcement of the provision. Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 310. We generally agree. Disclosing one's social media accounts—including ones that are maintained pseudonymously—forfeits anonymity in that realm. Conditioning a concealed carry license on such a disclosure imposes a burden on the right to bear arms that is without sufficient analogue in our Nation's history or tradition of firearms regulation.
At the outset, it is important to be clear about what the social media provision does and does not require. All that this provision demands is a “list of ․ accounts,” N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(o)(iv), which we understand to mean the platforms the applicants use and the names under which they post (in modern parlance, their “handles”). It does not compel applicants to provide a password to their accounts, make their posts accessible to the public, or give a licensing officer permission to view non-public posts (such as by “friending” the officer or accepting a request to “follow” the applicant). No such requirements appear in the statute, and the State has consistently disclaimed any such obligation for applicants. See Nigrelli Br. at 45–46 (“The law requires only that applicants identify the existence of recent social-media accounts ․ The CCIA does not permit a licensing officer to see ․ restricted social-media accounts.”); Nigrelli Reply Br. at 17–18 (“[T]he social-media provision does not require disclosure of any non-public material from social-media accounts. ․ The provision requires only a list of accounts that would allow a licensing official to review information that applicants have already chosen to disclose publicly.”). And licensing officers, like anybody else, may review an applicant's public social media posts at their leisure without the aid of § 400.00(1)(o)(iv). This distinction appears to have been lost on Sloane, who devotes much attention to the requirement of “access” to social media. See Appellee Nigrelli Br. at 35–38.
On the other hand, compelled disclosure of pseudonymous social media handles to a licensing officer is no small burden. It is uncontroversial that the First Amendment protects the right to speak anonymously. Cornelio v. Connecticut, 32 F.4th 160, 169–70 (2d Cir. 2022) (reiterating a speaker's First Amendment interest in anonymity and holding that a requirement that a sex offender report all online “communication identifier[s]” burdened protected speech); see generally McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm'n, 514 U.S. 334, 341–43, 115 S.Ct. 1511, 131 L.Ed.2d 426 (1995); Talley v. California, 362 U.S. 60, 64–65, 80 S.Ct. 536, 4 L.Ed.2d 559 (1960). Anyone familiar with most social media platforms knows that nearly all handles are pseudonymous, at least to the extent that the poster's identity is not immediately apparent. To require disclosure of handles is thus to demand that applicants effectively forfeit their right to pseudonymous speech on social media (where so much speech now takes place).
That significant burden on the right to bear arms is not one for which we see persuasive historical analogues. The State points to no historical law conditioning lawful carriage of a firearm on disclosing one's pseudonyms or, more generally, on informing the government about one's history of speech. That historical silence is telling because, as the district court explained at length, the Founders were familiar with pseudonymous publishing, including of “virulent political pamphlets” and other “controversial writings,” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 309. Yet neither the Founders nor successive generations required forfeiture of a speaker's anonymity in order to facilitate an inquiry into character or dangerousness. This constitutes “relevant evidence that the challenged regulation is inconsistent with the Second Amendment.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 26, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
The State argues more generally that review of social media is consistent with a tradition of licensing officers “looking to past conduct, associates, and reputation to assess whether an applicant is law-abiding and responsible.” Nigrelli Br. at 44. That is true, so far as it goes: social media posts can be relevant to assessing character and reputation. But review of these posts is not the burden imposed by § 400.00(1)(o)(iv). The burden is the disclosure of pseudonyms under which applicants have a constitutional right to post their views. That is a burden analytically distinct from (and more severe than) the burden of a licensing officer reviewing applicants’ publicly available posts.
The State also asks for flexibility in our historical inquiry because “[t]he development of social media is a quintessential dramatic technological change,” which requires “a nuanced analogical approach.” Nigrelli Br. at 44 (citing Bruen, 597 U.S. at 27, 142 S.Ct. 2111); see also supra Background § III.F. Social media is of course revolutionary because of the ease with which individuals can disseminate their thoughts to a large audience without the traditional barriers to publishing. That is indeed a break from the practice of publishing newspaper pieces as “Publius”—we grant that Facebook likely would have baffled the Founders. But the CCIA's social media requirement does not bear upon the aspects of social media that are new. While social media writ large may have no historical analogue, social media handles do. The frequency, formality, and barriers to dissemination of one's views may be different, but the election of a pseudonym to hide one's true identity is not.
The State is not wrong that posting on social media in the twenty-first century is different from publishing on physical media in the nineteenth century. Social media posts are frequently of a very different character from the well-crafted pamphlets known to students of the Ratification debates. And the spontaneity of speech on social media, without editors or filters, may indeed lead to a greater frequency of messages that are relevant to an assessment of character and dangerousness. See Amicus Br. of Dr. Jaclyn Schildkraut (discussing social science research indicating that social media posts “provide[ ] insights into intended behavior, and that an examination of potential social media [content] can provide an early warning sign of potential future violence”). But those considerations of relevance or usefulness cannot overcome the absence of any analogous disclosure requirement from the historical record combined with the constitutional interests implicated by the mandatory disclosure of online pseudonyms.
In sum, we agree with the district court that Plaintiffs are likely to succeed on the merits of their constitutional challenge to this provision, and we AFFIRM the district court's preliminary injunction as it applies to the social media requirement.
SENSITIVE LOCATIONS
We now consider the Plaintiffs’ challenges to assorted subsections of N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-e banning the carriage of firearms in “sensitive locations.”59
Standing is a significant issue with respect to many of the sensitive location challenges. No plaintiff has been arrested or prosecuted under § 265.01-e, but “an actual arrest, prosecution, or other enforcement action is not a prerequisite to challenging the law.” Susan B. Anthony List v. Driehaus, 573 U.S. 149, 158, 134 S.Ct. 2334, 189 L.Ed.2d 246 (2014). Instead, a plaintiff has Article III standing to bring a pre-enforcement challenge to a criminal statute if he or she can “demonstrate: (1) ‘an intention to engage in a course of conduct arguably affected with a constitutional interest’; (2) that the intended conduct is ‘proscribed by’ the challenged law; and (3) that ‘there exists a credible threat of prosecution thereunder.’ ” Vitagliano v. County of Westchester, 71 F.4th 130, 136 (2d Cir. 2023) (quoting Driehaus, 573 U.S. at 159, 134 S.Ct. 2334).
We discuss many standing issues below as they arise, usually relating to intention and proscription. But we consider at the outset the need for a “credible threat of prosecution,” as it cuts across all of plaintiffs’ challenges. The various verbal formulations elaborating this standard tend to be unhelpful. We have said that “credible threat” means that the “fear of criminal prosecution ․ is not imaginary or wholly speculative.” Hedges v. Obama, 724 F.3d 170, 196 (2d Cir. 2013) (quoting Babbitt v. United Farm Workers Nat'l Union, 442 U.S. 289, 302, 99 S.Ct. 2301, 60 L.Ed.2d 895 (1979)). And a credible threat is missing where “plaintiffs do not claim that they have ever been threatened with prosecution, that a prosecution is likely, or even that a prosecution is remotely possible.” Knife Rights, 802 F.3d at 384.
Such statements could be overread to require a rigorous inquiry into the chances that a given plaintiff will be prosecuted. But Article III is satisfied by much less. In Babbitt v. United Farm Workers National Union, the Supreme Court found pre-enforcement standing without much evidence suggesting that a prosecution was either imminent or particularly likely. There, a labor group challenged a law criminalizing “dishonest, untruthful, and deceptive publicity.” 442 U.S. at 302, 99 S.Ct. 2301. The plaintiff organization “ha[d] actively engaged in consumer publicity campaigns in the past,” “alleged ․ an intention to continue to engage in boycott activities,” and stated that although it did “not plan to propagate untruths ․ erroneous statement is inevitable in free debate.” Id. at 301, 99 S.Ct. 2301 (internal quotation marks omitted). The Court acknowledged that the challenged law “has not yet been applied and may never be applied” but nonetheless found an Article III case or controversy because “the State ha[d] not disavowed any intention of invoking the criminal penalty provision against unions that commit unfair labor practices.” Id. at 302, 99 S.Ct. 2301. The timorous organization was “thus not without some reason in fearing prosecution,” and its fears were “not imaginary or wholly speculative.” Id.
Babbitt demonstrates that the “credible threat of prosecution” is a “quite forgiving” requirement that sets up only a “low threshold” for a plaintiff to surmount. Hedges, 724 F.3d at 197 (quoting N.H. Right to Life Pol. Action Comm. v. Gardner, 99 F.3d 8, 14–15 (1st Cir. 1996)); see also id. at 200 (“[N]either this Court nor the Supreme Court has required much to establish this final step ․”). Courts have “not place[d] the burden on the plaintiff to show an intent by the government to enforce the law against it” but rather “presumed such intent in the absence of a disavowal by the government.” Id. at 197; accord Vitagliano, 71 F.4th at 138 (“[W]here a statute specifically proscribes conduct, the law of standing does not place the burden on the plaintiff to show an intent by the government to enforce the law against it.” (quoting Tweed-New Haven Airport Auth. v. Tong, 930 F.3d 65, 71 (2d Cir. 2019))). That is, “courts are generally ‘willing to presume that the government will enforce the law as long as the relevant statute is recent and not moribund.’ ” Cayuga Nation, 824 F.3d at 331 (quoting Hedges, 724 F.3d at 197).
To be sure, some of our recent decisions regarding pre-enforcement standing have relied on more specific indications that enforcement can be expected. For example, in Silva v. Farrish, we explained that the plaintiffs had “already been subject to fines and enforcement proceedings for violating the fishing regulations” that they challenged. 47 F.4th 78, 87 (2d Cir. 2022). Similarly, the plaintiffs in Knife Rights had previously been charged under the challenged statute, and one plaintiff had been party to a deferred prosecution agreement which “expressly threatened future charges if its terms were not satisfied,” 802 F.3d at 385–86. And in Cayuga Nation, the government had specifically “announced its intention to enforce the Ordinance against the Nation” as well as the group headed by the lead individual plaintiff. 824 F.3d at 331 (citation omitted).
Here, one defendant argues that such indicia of future prosecution are required to show standing and, accordingly, that at least some plaintiffs lack standing because they have “failed to establish [that they have] been threatened with certain ․ prosecution pursuant to the CCIA.” Cecile Br. at 15–16. The principal support advanced for that position is a summary order that (by its nature) lacks precedential force and that, in any event, lacks persuasive force in this case.60 But we rejected that very position in Vitagliano v. County of Westchester: “While evidence [that a plaintiff faced either previous enforcement actions or a stated threat of future prosecution] is, of course, relevant to assessing the credibility of an enforcement threat, none of these cases suggest that such evidence is necessary to make out an injury in fact.” 71 F.4th at 139 (citing Driehaus, 573 U.S. at 164, 134 S.Ct. 2334); accord id. (“[R]equiring an ‘overt threat to enforce’ a criminal prohibition ‘would run afoul of the Supreme Court's admonition not to put the challenger to the choice between abandoning his rights or risking prosecution.’ ” (some quotation marks omitted) (quoting Tong, 930 F.3d at 70)). Instead, we reiterated that, although “the presumption that the government will enforce its own laws ‘in and of itself, is not sufficient to confer standing,’ ” id. (quoting Adam v. Barr, 792 F. App'x 20, 23 (2d. Cir. 2019) (summary order)), “we ‘presume such intent [to enforce the law] in the absence of a disavowal by the government or another reason to conclude that no such intent existed.’ ” Id. at 138 (quoting Tong, 930 F.3d at 71).
Babbitt and Vitagliano control this case. In Babbitt, the state of Arizona had not specifically threatened the plaintiff organization with criminal sanctions, had never prosecuted anyone under the challenged provision, and had acknowledged it might never do so. See 442 U.S. at 301–02, 99 S.Ct. 2301. The plaintiff then averred an intention only to risk lawbreaking, and the state had not disavowed prosecution. If those facts alone are enough to render a fear of prosecution more than “imaginary or wholly speculative,” id. at 302, 99 S.Ct. 2301, then so must the Plaintiffs’ allegations here. See Seegars v. Gonzales, 396 F.3d 1248, 1252 (D.C. Cir. 2005) (“[Babbitt] appeared to find a threat of prosecution credible on the basis that plaintiffs’ intended behavior is covered by the statute and the law is generally enforced. Courts have often found that combination enough[.]”). And like the plaintiff in Vitagliano, the Plaintiffs here challenge a law “enacted ․ just months before [they] brought this action” which is “designed to curb the very conduct in which [they] intend[ ] to engage”; “there is no indication that the [defendants] ha[ve] disavowed enforcement” of the challenged law; and we have “no reason to doubt that the [State] will enforce its recently enacted law against those who violate its terms.” 71 F.4th at 138–39.
The Plaintiffs have surmounted the “low” and “quite forgiving” bar for pre-enforcement standing with respect to many of the CCIA's challenged provisions. Hedges, 724 F.3d at 197. While the statements by law enforcement officials cited by Plaintiffs may not directly threaten the specific Plaintiffs in these cases with arrest, those statements are, in the context of this case, evidence that Plaintiffs face a realistic threat of arrest and prosecution. Far from disavowing prosecution of Plaintiffs, multiple Defendants have announced their intention to enforce the CCIA,61 and the Superintendent of State Police has warned that his department will have “zero tolerance” for violations. Although prosecution is not certain, Plaintiffs articulate a plausible chain of events resulting in their arrest and prosecution: the “brazen nature of [their] intended defiance,” in the district court's words, makes it likely to be noticed by citizens and then by police. E.g., Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 263.62 Plaintiffs “are thus not without some reason in fearing prosecution,” and their fears are neither “imaginary [n]or wholly speculative.” Babbitt, 442 U.S. at 302, 99 S.Ct. 2301.
For those reasons, we conclude that the Plaintiffs here have adequately demonstrated a credible threat of enforcement—each Plaintiff will accordingly have standing if he can also show “an intention to engage in a course of conduct arguably affected with a constitutional interest” and “that the intended conduct is proscribed by the challenged law.” Vitagliano, 71 F.4th at 136 (quotation marks omitted). With that settled, we proceed to Plaintiffs’ various challenges to § 265.01-e’s sensitive location restrictions.
I. Treatment Centers
Section 265.01-e(2)(b) prohibits possession of a gun in any “location providing health, behavioral health, or chemical dep[e]ndance care or services.” We first consider standing.
A. Standing
The district court found that only Joseph Mann has standing to challenge paragraph (2)(b).63 Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 265. Mann, a pastor at Fellowship Baptist Church in Parish, NY, averred that his church “provides an addiction recovery ministry” through an organization called “RU Recovery.” J.A. 181 (Mann Decl. ¶ 28). This ministry “ha[s] brought persons in the program to church property for counseling and care.” Id. at 181–82 (Mann Decl. ¶¶ 28–29). It is not clear whether Mann personally provides counseling in these sessions, but Mann does allege that the church (his workplace) is a “location providing chemical depend[e]nce care or services” when hosting the RU Recovery program and that Mann “intend[s] to continue to possess and carry [his] firearm while” at the church, J.A. 177, 181 (Mann Decl. ¶¶ 11, 29). The State, by contrast, contends that the church is not a qualifying location providing “behavioral health or chemical depend[e]nce care or services,” because the RU Recovery program “is intended to encourage [participants] ‘to seek help and voluntarily enter treatment’ ” rather than “to provide treatment.” Nigrelli Br. at 49–50 (quoting J.A. 181 (Mann Decl. ¶ 28)).
In determining Mann's standing, we are not called on to offer a definitive or comprehensive interpretation of the CCIA.64 “[C]ourts are to consider whether the plaintiff's intended conduct is ‘arguably proscribed’ by the challenged statute, not whether the intended conduct is in fact proscribed.” Picard v. Magliano, 42 F.4th 89, 98 (2d Cir. 2022) (quoting Driehaus, 573 U.S. at 162, 134 S.Ct. 2334). Thus, “if a plaintiff's interpretation of a statute is reasonable enough[,] and under that interpretation, the plaintiff may legitimately fear that it will face enforcement of the statute, then the plaintiff has standing to challenge the statute.” Id. (internal quotation marks omitted). In making that determination, we do not defer to the government's interpretation of the statute, Vt. Right to Life Comm., Inc. v. Sorrell, 221 F.3d 376, 383 (2d Cir. 2000) (finding plaintiff's interpretation “reasonable enough” even though contradicted by the state), or to its representations regarding the likelihood of a particular prosecution, id. (“The State also argues that ․ [it] has no intention of suing [plaintiff] for its activities. While that may be so, there is nothing that prevents the State from changing its mind. It is not forever bound, by estoppel or otherwise, to the view of the law that it asserts in this litigation.”).
Mann's allegations suffice under this forgiving standard. Paragraph (2)(b) is intentionally broad: rather than applying only to locations providing “treatment,” as the State would have it, the law refers to “care or services.” The RU Recovery program may not provide “chemical depend[e]nce care,” but addiction counseling is at least arguably a “chemical depend[e]nce service.” Since Mann has alleged an intention to violate the law by carrying a gun at a location that (arguably) “provid[es] ․ chemical depend[e]nce ․ services” (and he faces a “credible threat” of prosecution for the reasons explained above), he has standing to seek an injunction against enforcement of paragraph (2)(b).
B. Merits
1. District Court Decision
We now turn to the merits of Mann's challenge to § 265.01-e(2)(b). The district court found that the plain text of the Second Amendment covered the conduct proscribed by § 265.01-e(2)(b)—i.e., licensed carriage of a concealed firearm for self-defense in a location providing behavioral health, or chemical dependence care or services—and accordingly placed the burden on the State to demonstrate the statute's consistency with this Nation's tradition of firearm regulation.65 The State, in turn, offered two categories of historical analogues. First, the State pointed to an 1837 Massachusetts militia law, an 1837 Maine militia law, and an 1843 Rhode Island militia law that each excluded people with intellectual disabilities, mental illnesses, and alcohol addictions from militia service. Second, the State generally referenced the tradition of restricting firearms in locations frequented by vulnerable populations such as children and provided, as examples, state statutes prohibiting firearms in school rooms.
Assuming, without deciding, that the State's proffered analogues were sufficiently established and representative to constitute a national tradition, the district court nonetheless rejected the two groups of analogues as insufficiently similar to the challenged provision. For one, the district court determined that the purposes of the state militia laws were different from that of § 265.01-e(2)(b) in that the militia laws were concerned with keeping firearms out of the hands of individuals with intellectual disabilities, mental health issues, and alcoholism, whereas § 265.01-e(2)(b) prohibits law-abiding, licensed individuals from carrying their firearms in places providing behavioral health or chemical dependence care or services. Even putting aside this difference in purpose, the district court concluded that § 265.01-e(2)(b) burdened Second Amendment rights more than did the state militia laws because, while the state militia laws took firearms out of the hands of individuals with the above-listed conditions only during wartime, § 265.01-e(2)(b) precludes all licensed carriers from ever bringing their firearm into a behavioral health or chemical dependence service center.
The district court likewise rejected the tradition of regulating firearms in locations frequented by vulnerable populations such as children. Because the State had not adduced any evidence showing that more children are present in places of behavioral and substance dependence care today than in the 18th and 19th centuries, the court found that the absence of 18th- and 19th-century regulations prohibiting firearms in medical establishments indicated that the historical tradition of regulating firearms out of a concern for children has not traditionally extended so far as to justify regulation in medical establishments.
Finally, because both medical establishments and gun violence existed in the 18th- and 19th-centuries, the district court considered the lack of evidence as to historical firearm bans “in places such as ‘almshouses,’ hospitals, or physician's offices,” as “evidence of th[e] regulation's inconsistency with the Second Amendment.” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 318.
2. The State's Historical Analogues
a. Well-Established and Representative
Because the district court only assumed, without deciding, that the State's proposed analogues were representative and established, we begin there. “[A]nalogical reasoning requires only that the government identify a well-established and representative historical analogue.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (emphasis removed). Representativeness and establishment ensure against “endorsing outliers that our ancestors would never have accepted.” Id. (internal quotation marks omitted). On the other hand, as Bruen cautioned, these requirements cannot be stretched to require the historical twin or “dead ringer.” Id.
Despite assuming that the State's proffered analogues were sufficiently well-established and representative, the district court expressed some skepticism as to this conclusion. First, it questioned whether laws from three states could constitute an established tradition. Second, due to the population size of those three states relative to that of the Nation, it doubted these laws were representative.66 We do not share these skepticisms. True, Bruen did utilize the number of states with analogous regulations and their relative populations as indicia of the orthodoxy and representativeness of New York's proper-cause requirement, but New York's requirement was exceptional in both the way and the extent to which it burdened Second Amendment rights. As we have already noted, less exceptional regulations permit a “more nuanced approach.” Id. at 27, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
Lacking any evidence that the laws from Maine, Massachusetts, and Rhode Island were historical anomalies, we find them sufficiently established and representative to stand as analogues.67 Compare id. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“Although the historical record yields relatively few 18th- and 19th-century ‘sensitive places’ where weapons were altogether prohibited ․ we are also aware of no disputes regarding the lawfulness of such prohibitions.” (emphasis added)), with id. at 67, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“the bare existence of these localized restrictions cannot overcome the overwhelming evidence of an otherwise enduring American tradition permitting public carry” (emphasis added)). Disqualifying proffered analogues based only on strict quantitative measures such as population size absent any other indication of historical deviation would turn Bruen into the very “regulatory straightjacket” the Court warned against. Id. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111; see also supra Licensing Regime § III.A.2 (rejecting view that percentage of population governed is dispositive and instead explaining that this consideration “is only one clue to whether said law may have been an outlier unable to refute a contrary tradition”).
b. Consistency with Tradition
Both sets of the State's proffered analogues place § 265.01-e(2)(b) within this Nation's tradition of firearm regulation in locations where vulnerable populations are present. We begin by comparing how and why § 265.01-e(2)(b) and each set of the proffered historical analogues burdens Second Amendment rights. Section 265.01-e(2)(b) aims to protect “vulnerable or impaired people who either cannot defend themselves or cannot be trusted to have firearms around them safely.” Nigrelli Br. at 62. It does so by prohibiting carriage of firearms in centers providing behavioral health or substance dependence services. As to the 19th-century state militia laws, the State argues that the statutes of Maine, Massachusetts, and Rhode Island, which prohibited those with mental illness, intellectual disabilities, and alcohol addiction from serving in militias, were aimed at protecting vulnerable populations from either misusing arms or having arms used against them.68 These statutes operated by preventing such individuals from serving in the militia. See J.A. 635 (Mass. Gen. Laws ch. 240, § 1 (1837)); J.A. 639 (1837 Me. Laws 424); J.A. 644 (1843 R.I. Pub. Laws 1). Similarly, the State claims that the tradition of regulating firearms in locations frequented by children, as exemplified by historical regulations prohibiting guns in schools, is motivated by the need to protect a vulnerable population.69 This category of laws operated by preventing the carriage of firearms in places of education or school rooms. See, e.g., J.A. 602 (1870 Tex. Gen. Laws 63, ch. 46); J.A. 611 (1883 Mo. Sess. Laws 76); J.A. 617 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 17, § 3); J.A. 621 (1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, § 7).
The three militia laws and the tradition of prohibiting firearms in schools are each “relevantly similar” to § 265.01-e(2)(b). The relevantly similar features of those statutes prohibiting firearms in schools are the burden they place on Second Amendment rights and the reason: prohibiting firearm carriage for the protection of vulnerable populations.70 The relevantly similar feature of the state militia laws is who has historically been considered to make up a vulnerable population justifying firearm regulation on their behalf, i.e., the mentally ill or those with substance use disorders.71
In this case, both analogues suffice to validate our finding of the likely constitutionality of § 265.01-e(2)(b). Had the State pointed only to those laws prohibiting firearms in schools, the State would have had to demonstrate that individuals with behavioral and substance abuse disorders are sufficiently analogous to children protected by school carriage prohibitions, as the State cannot justify a sensitive location prohibition merely by designating a population as “vulnerable” and enacting a law purporting to protect them. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (emphasizing that “analogical reasoning under the Second Amendment” is not a “blank check”). However, the evidence from the state militia laws that individuals with behavioral or substance dependence disorders have historically been viewed as a vulnerable population justifying firearm regulation makes such analogical reasoning unnecessary to our holding.72 Likewise, had the State pointed only to the militia law analogues, which disarmed the members of the vulnerable population itself rather than others in proximity, it would have borne the burden of demonstrating that § 265.01-e(2)(b)—which disarms everyone in spaces where a vulnerable population is present—is consistent with or distinctly similar to a historical tradition.
In sum, the State's evidence establishes a tradition of prohibiting firearms in locations where vulnerable populations congregate and a concomitant tradition of considering those with behavioral and substance dependence disorders to constitute a vulnerable population justifying firearm regulation. Section 265.01-e(2)(b) is consistent with these traditions.
3. Proper Analysis of Proffered Analogues
In rejecting the State's evidence as to the tradition of regulating firearms in places frequented by vulnerable populations such as children, the district court misidentified the relevantly similar features of the State's proffered analogues The district court found that the State failed to show that today's treatment centers contain more children than similar locales in the 18th- and 19th-centuries; but the relevantly similar feature of these analogues is the how and the why: firearm prohibition (how) in places frequented by and for the protection of vulnerable populations (why). The New York legislature need not have attempted to protect the exact same subset of vulnerable persons for its regulation to be relevantly similar to these historical analogues. Similarly, the district court discounted the state militia laws on the ground that they impose a lesser burden on Second Amendment rights than § 265.01-e(2)(b); but the relevantly similar feature of the state militia laws is that the intellectually disabled, mentally ill, or those with substance use disorders have historically been considered a vulnerable population justifying firearm regulation. In requiring both sets of the State's analogues to burden Second Amendment rights on behalf of the exact same group in the very same way, the district court disregarded Bruen’s caution that “even if a modern-day regulation is not a dead ringer for historical precursors, it still may be analogous enough to pass constitutional muster.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
Furthermore, contrary to the district court's conclusion, the State was not required to show that firearms were traditionally banned “in places such as ‘almshouses,’ hospitals, or physician's offices.” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 318. For one, this requirement by the district court was a product of its erroneous conclusion that the State's evidence was insufficiently analogous. Properly construed, that evidence establishes a historical tradition of firearm regulation embracing § 265.01-e(2)(b)—the opposite of historical silence. Yet, even putting that foundational error aside, the district court made too much of Bruen’s observation that “when a challenged regulation addresses a general societal problem that has persisted since the 18th century, the lack of a distinctly similar historical regulation addressing that problem is relevant evidence that the challenged regulation is inconsistent with the Second Amendment.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 26, 142 S.Ct. 2111. See also supra Background § III.F.
* * *
For the above stated reasons, the preliminary injunction is VACATED insofar as the State was enjoined from enforcing § 265.01-e(2)(b) in behavioral health and substance dependence care and service centers.
II. Places of Worship
Section 265.01-e(2)(c) of the CCIA criminalizes possession of a firearm in “any place of worship, except for those persons responsible for security at such place of worship.” N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-e(2)(c). Plaintiff Joseph Mann avers that, as pastor, he frequently carries a concealed firearm in his church, the Fellowship Baptist Church in Parish, New York, and that he intends to continue doing so notwithstanding the CCIA's prohibition on carrying firearms in places of worship. J.A. 72 ¶¶ 182–83. The district court held that the place of worship provision intruded on Mann's Second Amendment right to carry firearms and that the State had failed to produce sufficient evidence of a historical tradition of analogous firearm regulations. It thus enjoined the defendants from enforcing the provision.73 Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 321. The State now appeals the grant of that preliminary injunction. It does not dispute Mann's standing to challenge the place of worship provision, and we see no impediment to standing.
A. Standing and Mootness
The New York legislature amended the place of worship provision after the district courts enjoined it. Previously, the provision criminalized possession of a firearm in “any place of worship or religious observation.” 2023 N.Y. Laws, Ch. 55, pt. F, § 4. Effective May 3, 2023, however, places of “religious observation” are no longer covered, and the provision has an exception for “those persons responsible for security at such place of worship.” Id. We must consider whether the statutory amendment has mooted Mann's claims.
We conclude that it has. Put simply, the amended statute does not prohibit Mann from doing what he seeks to do. “A case is moot when the issues presented are no longer live or the parties lack a legally cognizable interest in the outcome.” Tann v. Bennett, 807 F.3d 51, 52 (2d Cir. 2015) (internal quotation marks omitted). It remains live if “a court can fashion some form of meaningful relief to award the complaining party.” Exxon Mobil Corp. v. Healey, 28 F.4th 383, 392 (2d Cir. 2022) (internal quotation marks omitted).
Plaintiff Mann alleges that his church “maintained a church security team, consisting of trusted church members ․ designated to carry their firearms to provide security and protection to the congregation,” and that he “intends to continue to possess and carry [his] firearm while on church property” notwithstanding the place of worship provision. J.A. 72 ¶¶ 182–83 (alteration in original) (quotation marks omitted). That is exactly what the amended statute allows Mann to do; he can freely designate himself and the church security team as “persons responsible for security,” N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-e(2)(c), and thereby except them from the scope of the CCIA's criminal prohibition. Accordingly, Mann's challenge to the place of worship provision is moot.74 No other Plaintiff has standing to support the district court's injunction against that provision.
B. Vacatur of Preliminary Injunctions
With the subsequent mooting of Plaintiffs’ request for a preliminary injunction, the question remains as to the nature of our mandate—whether to vacate or affirm the injunctions. “In considering whether vacatur is inappropriate, our primary concern is the fault of the parties in causing the appeal to become moot.” Russman v. Bd. of Educ. of Enlarged City Sch. Dist. of Watervliet, 260 F.3d 114, 121 (2d Cir. 2001). Vacatur is appropriate “in those cases where review is ‘prevented through happenstance’ and not through circumstances attributable to any of the parties.” Haley v. Pataki, 60 F.3d 137, 142 (2d Cir. 1995) (“Here, mootness resulted neither from happenstance nor from settlement from the entire action, but from the Governor's voluntary compliance with the preliminary injunction. Under the circumstances of this case, vacatur of the injunction is proper.”).
The amendment of the place of worship provision is not attributable to any named defendant in any of the cases on appeal; it is the product of the New York legislature's intervention. Most importantly, none of the New York officers named as defendants made a voluntary choice to discontinue their enforcement of the prior place of worship provision—which decision could one day be reversed, and the issues thereby revived. The challenged law is gone, and there is no possibility that the defendants could seek to enforce it against the Plaintiffs. Under these circumstances, vacatur of the district courts’ injunctions is warranted.
* * *
For the reasons set forth above, we VACATE the district court's preliminary injunction against enforcement of § 265.01-e(2)(c).75
III. Parks and Zoos
New York also criminalizes possession of a gun in “public parks[ ] and zoos.” N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-e(2)(d). Plaintiffs challenge the constitutionality of this prohibition. We first address standing and then the merits of this challenge.
A. Standing
Defendant Joseph Cecile, Chief of the Syracuse Police Department, disputes the district court's conclusion that Plaintiff Corey Johnson has standing with respect to the zoo prohibition, arguing that Johnson (1) did not adequately allege his intention to visit a zoo; and (2) has not shown a credible threat of enforcement by Cecile (as opposed to by other law enforcement officials).76
Johnson averred in his declaration that he and his wife “frequently visit the Rosamond Gifford Zoo in Syracuse, at least once or twice every fall, so that my wife can see the otters and wolves, which are her favorites.” J.A. 139–40 (Johnson Decl. ¶ 17). He then estimated that they would “visit the zoo this fall as well, at least once, within the next 90 days.” Id. And since he “intend[s] to carry [his] firearm when [they] visit the Rosamond Gifford Zoo,” id., he alleges that he faces a credible threat of being prosecuted for violating paragraph (2)(d).
Johnson's averments are in line with the kinds of allegations that the Supreme Court has found sufficient to support pre-enforcement standing. In Babbitt v. United Farm Workers National Union, the plaintiff organization did not even allege an intention to violate the law: it merely stated its “intention to continue to engage in [lawful] boycott activities” and that an erroneous statement criminalized by the statute is “inevitable in free debate.” 442 U.S. at 301, 99 S.Ct. 2301 (internal quotation marks omitted). The Court has also recognized that plaintiffs who intend to comply with the law solely to avoid prosecution (i.e., who have been deterred) have standing to bring a pre-enforcement challenge. See Holder v. Humanitarian L. Project, 561 U.S. 1, 15–16, 130 S.Ct. 2705, 177 L.Ed.2d 355 (2010) (finding standing based on allegation that plaintiffs would resume proscribed conduct “if the statute's allegedly unconstitutional bar were lifted”); Steffel v. Thompson, 415 U.S. 452, 456, 94 S.Ct. 1209, 39 L.Ed.2d 505 (1974) (“Petitioner alleged in his complaint that, although he desired to return to the shopping center to distribute handbills, he had not done so because of his concern that he, too, would be arrested.”). Johnson's averments, while short of pleading the time and date of his intended visit to the zoo, are more specific than the allegations found sufficient in Babbitt, Holder, and Steffel. He has therefore adequately pled his “intention to engage in a course of conduct arguably affected with a constitutional interest, but proscribed by a statute.” Driehaus, 573 U.S. at 159, 134 S.Ct. 2334.
As to a credible threat of enforcement by Defendant Cecile (or, by extension, the Syracuse Police Department), Cecile adduces two arguments. He argues first that he has made no “concrete and particularized statement to the general public regarding the imminence of anyone's arrest, let alone [regarding] Plaintiff Johnson ․,” Cecile Br. at 14 (internal quotation marks omitted), and thus that Johnson's fear of arrest by the Syracuse Police is unduly speculative. But (as explained above) the bar for stating a credible threat of enforcement is “low” and “quite forgiving.” Hedges, 724 F.3d at 197. It is not necessary that a plaintiff be specifically threatened with prosecution. Moreover, far from “disavow[ing] any intention of invoking” the challenged law, Babbitt, 442 U.S. at 302, 99 S.Ct. 2301, Cecile has expressly stated that he and his officers will enforce the CCIA, albeit not proactively. J.A. 24 (Compl. ¶ 24); see also J.A. 237 (“ ‘It will be complaint-driven,’ [Cecile] said.”). A lack of enthusiasm or initiative does not rebut the presumption “that the government will enforce the law as long as the relevant statute is recent and not moribund.” Cayuga Nation, 824 F.3d at 331 (quoting Hedges, 724 F.3d at 197).
Second, Cecile argues that the Rosamond Gifford Zoo is on county (rather than city) land and thus falls under the jurisdiction of the Onondaga County Sheriff and Park Rangers. But this fact is not fatal to Johnson's standing: Cecile has conceded that Syracuse police are not barred from responding to complaints at the Zoo. See Cecile Mem. of L. in Opp. to Mot. to Dismiss at 9, Antonyuk, No. 22-cv-986, ECF No. 47-9. Like the district court, we “ha[ve] little doubt that, if there were a gun incident reported at the zoo, the Syracuse Police Department would promptly respond (in addition to any County Park Ranger available).” 639 F. Supp. 3d at 272. While the County's primary jurisdiction over the zoo might alleviate somewhat Johnson's fear of arrest by the Syracuse Police, it does not render the threat of enforcement by Cecile or the Syracuse Police “imaginary or wholly speculative,” Babbitt, 442 U.S. at 302, 99 S.Ct. 2301, and is therefore not of constitutional moment. Accordingly, Johnson has standing with respect to Cecile's threatened enforcement of the zoo prohibition.
B. Merits
1. District Court Decision
Having determined that the conduct proscribed by § 265.01-e(2)(d), i.e., carriage in public parks and zoos, was within the plain text of the Second Amendment, the district court placed the burden on the State to establish the regulation's consistency with the Nation's history and tradition. The district court considered the following analogues: (1) an 1870 Texas law prohibiting firearms in “place[s] where persons are assembled for educational, literary or scientific purposes,” J.A. 602 (1870 Tex. Gen. Laws 63, ch. 46); (2) an 1883 Missouri Law prohibiting carriage in places where people assembled for “educational, literary or social purposes” and “any other public assemblage of persons met for any lawful purpose,” J.A. 611 (1883 Mo. Sess. Laws 76); (3) an 1889 Arizona law and 1890 Oklahoma law prohibiting carriage in any “place where persons are assembled for amusement or for educational or scientific purposes,” J.A. 617 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 17, § 3), see also J.A. 621 (1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, § 7); (4) ordinances in New York City, Philadelphia, St. Paul, Detroit, Chicago, Salt Lake City, St. Louis, and Pittsburgh adopted between 1861 and 1897 prohibiting carriage in public parks;77 and (5) the tradition of prohibiting firearms in schools.
Before proceeding to the individual history and analogue test for public parks and zoos,78 the district court noted that it would afford little weight to territorial laws and city ordinances that did not correspond to sufficiently similar state laws. Likewise, it discounted laws from the last decade of the 19th century because of their distance from the Founding and Reconstruction. Given these parameters, the district court considered: the 1870 Texas law, 1883 Missouri law, and “to a lesser extent” the New York, Philadelphia, Chicago, St. Louis, and St. Paul ordinances. Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 324.
The purpose of the analogous regulations, per the district court, “appears to have been to protect people from the danger and disturbance that may accompany firearms.” Id. The statutes and ordinances accomplished this purpose and accordingly burdened Second Amendment rights by “prohibiting the carrying of firearms (1) where people are assembled for educational or literary purposes, or (2) to a lesser extent, when people frequent an outdoor location for purpose of recreation or amusement (or travel through such a location), especially when children are present.” Id.
a. Public Parks
The district court rejected the State's arguments that its historical analogues supported banning carriage in public parks. As an initial matter, the court determined that the 1870 Texas and 1883 Missouri laws demonstrated neither an established tradition—because they were only two statutes—nor a representative one—because the combined population of those two states was only 6.6 percent of the American population at the time. Beyond that, the district court noted that neither statute specifically prohibited carriage in public parks. Because both states “[p]resumably ․ contained at least some public parks” at the time of the statutes’ passing, the district court found that this lack of a specific prohibition weighed against finding a tradition of firearm regulation in public parks. Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 325. The court also observed that statutes banning firearms in analogous places such as “commons” or “greens” were also absent from the historical record. Id. Given this, the district court did not take the Texas and Missouri statutes to support a tradition of banning carriage in public parks.
Nor did the city ordinances establish such a tradition, according to the district court. First, the district court stated that, to the extent such ordinances established any tradition of regulation at all, they would do so only for “public parks in a city” not those outside of cities. Id. Next, notwithstanding the support that the numerous ordinances did lend to prohibiting carriage in urban public parks, the district court determined that they did not set forth a well-established or representative tradition because the total population of the five cities in question accounted for only 6.8 percent of the population of the Nation at the time.
Finally, the district court dismissed the idea that the ordinances, when combined with the state statutes, could together demonstrate a well-established and representative tradition of prohibiting firearms in urban public parks, because the combined populations of the cities and states (13.4 percent) was under 15 percent of the national population.
b. Zoos
As with public parks, the district court held that the State's analogues failed to establish a tradition of regulating firearms in zoos. The court began by noting that the State did not offer any statutes explicitly prohibiting carriage in zoos, an absence deemed conspicuous by the district court, given that cities throughout the country appeared to have opened zoos in the latter half of the 19th century between 1864 to 1883. The district court also rejected the State's argument that, because three of these zoos were located within city parks, the city ordinances prohibiting firearms in public parks also supported regulations in zoos. According to the district court, the coverage of zoos by public park regulations indicated that zoos did not merit “more protection,” and therefore actually cut against finding a tradition of regulating firearms in zoos. Id. at 327. The court reiterated that, in any event, there was no well-established and representative history of regulating firearms in public parks, and thus no such tradition could be extended to zoos by virtue of their location in public parks.
The district court also rejected the State's attempt to liken zoos to playgrounds because of the presence of children. It found that the regulation in zoos is “more burdensome than the regulation in playgrounds, because adults more commonly frequent zoos without children than they frequent playgrounds without children.” Id.
* * *
Having found that the State failed to locate § 265.01-e’s prohibition on carriage in public parks and zoos within the Nation's tradition of firearm regulation, the district court enjoined the regulation's enforcement in both locations.
2. Analysis of the Historical Analogues — Public Parks
On appeal, the State offers three arguments for why its analogues show a history and tradition consistent with § 265.01-e. First, it argues that the regulation aims to protect the spaces where individuals often gather to express “their constitutional rights to protest or assemble” Nigrelli Br. at 61 (quoting § 265.01e(2)(s)). Thus, according to the State, the well-established tradition of regulating firearms in quintessential public forums, such as fairs and markets, justifies regulating firearms in public parks, which today often serve as public forums.79 As examples of this tradition, the State reaches as far back as a 1328 British statute forbidding going or riding “armed by night [ ]or by day, in fairs, markets.” Statute of Northampton 1328, 2 Edw. 3 c.3 (Eng.). The State adduces evidence that at least two Founding-era states and several Reconstruction-era states replicated this type of law, see J.A. 670 (1786 Va. Acts 35, Ch. 49); Collection of Statutes of the Parliament of England in Force in the State of North Carolina, pp. 60–61, ch. 3 (F. Martin Ed. 1792) (North Carolina Statute), as well as Reconstruction-era states, see J.A. 602 (1870 Tex. Gen. Laws 63, ch. 46); 611 (1883 Mo. Sess. Laws 76), 605–06 (1869 Tenn. Pub. Acts 23–24); 616–18 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 16–18); 621 (1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, § 7), and that, where challenged, these laws and subsequent amendments were upheld as constitutional by state courts. See, e.g., State v. Shelby, 90 Mo. 302, 2 S.W. 468, 469 (Mo. 1886), English v. State, 35 Tex. 473, 478–79 (1871); Andrews v. State, 50 Tenn. 165, 182 (1871). And, as it did below, the State offers the same eight city ordinances prohibiting firearms in city parks and notes that these ordinances were passed shortly after the time that parks emerged as municipal institutions.
Second, the State relies on the same state laws establishing a tradition of firearm regulation in public forums to argue that § 265.01-e(2)(d) is within the tradition of regulating firearms in “quintessentially” crowded places such as fairs and markets. Nigrelli Br. at 63.
Third, and finally, the State explains that § 265.01-e(2)(d) endeavors to protect children who often frequent public parks from firearms and is thus consistent with the tradition of regulating firearms in areas frequented by children.
We agree with the State that § 265.01-e is within the Nation's history of regulating firearms in quintessentially crowded areas and public forums, at least insofar as the regulation prohibits firearms in urban parks, though not necessarily as to rural parks. Considering, then, that the law has a plainly legitimate sweep as to urban parks, the facial challenge fails notwithstanding doubt that there is historical support for the regulation of firearms in wilderness parks, forests, and reserves.
a. Well-Established and Representative
Contrary to the district court's conclusion, the State has made a robust showing of a well-established and representative tradition of regulating firearms in public forums and quintessentially crowded places, enduring from medieval England to Reconstruction America and beyond.80 See Darrell A.H. Miller, Constitutional Conflict and Sensitive Places, 28 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 459, 475–76 (2019) (noting that regulations ensuring peaceable assembly have “a long history in Anglo-American jurisprudence” and noting a history of “general prohibitions on armaments” in public forums).
Though “[s]ometimes, in interpreting our own Constitution, it is better not to go too far back into antiquity,” that is distinctly not the case where “evidence shows that medieval law survived to become our Founders’ law.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 35, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (internal quotation marks omitted). Here, the State has shown that at least two states—Virginia and North Carolina—passed statutes at the Founding that replicated the medieval English law prohibiting firearms in fairs and markets,81 i.e., the traditional, crowded public forum.82 See J.A. 670 (1786 Va. Acts 35, Ch. 49) (prohibiting going or riding “armed by night [ ]or by day, in fairs or markets, ․ in terror of the county”); Collection of Statutes of the Parliament of England in Force in the State of North Carolina, pp. 60–61, ch. 3 (F. Martin Ed. 1792) (North Carolina law prohibiting “to go nor ride armed by night nor by day, in fairs, markets”).
The tradition of regulating firearms in quintessentially crowded places was continued throughout the history of our Nation. In Reconstruction, three states (Texas, Missouri, and Tennessee) passed laws prohibiting weapons in public forums and crowded places such as assemblies for “educational, literary or scientific purposes, or into a ball room, social party or other social gathering.” J.A. 602 (1870 Tex. Gen. Laws 63, ch. 46); see also id. at 605, 140 S.Ct. 2316 (1869 Tenn. Pub. Acts 23) (Tennessee law prohibiting the carriage of deadly weapons by “any person attending any fair, race course, or other public assembly of people”); id. at 611, 124 S.Ct. 1941 (1883 Mo. Sess. Laws 76) (Missouri law prohibiting weapons “where people are assembled for educational, literary or social purposes”). The territories of Oklahoma and Arizona did the same. See id. at 617, 124 S.Ct. 1941 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 17) (Arizona law prohibiting dangerous weapons “where persons are assembled for amusement or for educational or scientific purposes, or into any circus, show or public exhibition of any kind, or into a ball room, social party or social gathering”); id. at 621, 124 S.Ct. 1941 (1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, § 7) (Oklahoma law prohibiting carriage in places “where persons are assembled for ․ amusement, or for educational or scientific purposes, or into any circus, show or public exhibition of any kind, or into any ball room, or to any social party or social gathering”).
This “long, unbroken line,” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 35, 142 S.Ct. 2111, beginning from medieval England and extending beyond Reconstruction, indicates that the tradition of regulating firearms in often-crowded public forums is “part of the ‘immemorial’ custom” of this Nation, Miller, 28 WM. & MARY BILL RTS. J. at 476.
Of particular note, the state courts of all three states that had such laws upheld this type of statute as constitutional. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 68, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (noting that where state courts have passed on the constitutionality of a statute, we “know the basis of their perceived legality”). Holding an 1871 amendment to the 1870 Texas statute constitutional in English v. State, the Texas Supreme Court observed that “it appears [ ] little short of ridiculous, that any one should claim the right to carry upon his person” a firearm “into a peaceable public assembly, as for instance, into a church, a lecture room, a ball room, or any other place where ladies or gentleman are congregated together.”83 35 Tex. at 478–79. The same year, the Tennessee Supreme Court upheld Tennessee's statute by noting that “the private right to keep and use” arms “is limited by the duties and proprieties of social life” and that “[t]herefore, a man may well be prohibited from carrying his arms” to a “public assemblage.” Andrews, 50 Tenn. at 181–82. See also Shelby, 2 S.W. at 469 (holding that 1883 Mo. law prohibiting carriage “where people are assembled for educational, literary, or social purposes” was constitutional). English and Andrews tell us that the Nation not only tolerated the regulation of firearms in public forums and crowded spaces, but also found it aberrational that a state would be unable to regulate firearms to protect the “the duties and proprieties of social life” in such spaces. See Miller, 28 Wm. & Mary Bill. Rts. J. at 475 (“The idea of a right to peaceably assemble presumes ․ that such assemblages must be peaceable, as opposed to disorderly.”).
The number of states and territories with such statutes makes clear that this tradition has also been consistently representative of the Nation as a whole. At the time in which they were passed in 1791, Virginia's and North Carolina's statutes prohibiting firearms in fairs and markets applied to over a quarter of the Nation's population.84 By 1891, an additional three states and two territories had passed similar laws, meaning that such statutes applied to nearly 10 million Americans, a figure equivalent to about 15.3 percent of the Nation's population at that time.85 Cf. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 67, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (determining that the proffered analogues were not representative where they applied to only “about two-thirds of 1% of the population”).
In addition to showing that there existed a well-established and representative state tradition of such regulation, the State points to eight examples (Chicago, Detroit, New York City, Philadelphia, Pittsburgh, Salt Lake City, St. Paul, St. Louis) establishing a municipal tradition of regulating firearms in urban public parks specifically. The proliferation of these urban public park regulations between 1861 and 1897 coincides with the rise of public parks as municipal institutions over the latter half of the 19th century.86 While only 16 parks were created before 1800,87 “[f]ollowing the success of [New York's] Central Park, cities across the United States began building parks to meet recreational needs of residents[;] and during the second half of the 19th century, [Frederick Law] Olmsted and his partners [who planned Central Park] designed major parks or park systems in thirty cities.”88 David Schuyler, Summary of Parks in Urban America, Oxford Research Encyclopedia of American History (Nov. 3, 2015). As urban public parks took root as a new type of public forum, cities continued the tradition of regulating firearms in historical public forums, such as fairs and markets, to likewise keep these new public spaces, urban parks, peaceable.89 None of those city ordinances were invalidated by any court; indeed, we have not located any constitutional challenges to any of them. In other words, the ordinances were not merely adopted by legislative bodies in the respective cities in which they applied—they were apparently accepted without any constitutional objection by anyone. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“We therefore can assume it settled that these locations were ‘sensitive places’ where arms carrying could be prohibited” where we are “aware of no disputes regarding the lawfulness of such prohibitions.”).
The district court mistakenly discounted these city laws because they were not accompanied by state laws, relying on the Bruen majority's statement that “the bare existence of these localized restrictions cannot overcome the overwhelming evidence of an otherwise enduring American tradition.” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 323–24 (quoting Bruen, 597 U.S. at 67, 142 S.Ct. 2111). We think this is an overreading of Bruen. Bruen’s pronouncement addressed an isolated set of territorial laws, whose transient and temporary character does not correlate to the enduring municipal governments whose enactments are before us now. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 66–67, 142 S.Ct. 2111. And while Bruen also relied on the “miniscule” populations who were governed by the territorial statutes at issue, by 1897, fully eight percent of the entire population lived in the urban areas governed by the state's analogues here.90 See Dept. of Interior, Compendium of Eleventh Census: 1890, 2-452 tbls. 1–5 (1892). Moreover, the appropriate figure in this instance is not the percentage of the Nation's total population that was affected by city park firearms restrictions, but rather the percentage of the urban population that was governed by city park restrictions. By 1890, four of the five most populous cities prohibited firearms in their urban parks, and Brooklyn's incorporation into New York City in 1896 would result in all five of the most populous cities having such prohibitions. Id., Table 5 (New York, Chicago, Philadelphia, Brooklyn, and St. Louis). Those cities alone numbered over 4.9 million people, at a time when only 14 million Americans lived in a city with more than 25,000 inhabitants, resulting in at least 37.7% of the urban population living in cities where firearms were prohibited in their parks.
The upshot of the State's wealth of evidence is a well-established, representative, and longstanding tradition of regulating firearms in places that serve as public forums and, as a result, tend to be crowded. This tradition comes down to us from medieval England; it was enshrined in the law books of the largest (Virginia) and third largest (North Carolina) Founding-era states and built on throughout and beyond Reconstruction. Accord Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1901 (upholding firearm regulation given history of laws against “affrays,” including fighting in public or terroristic use of armaments, from medieval England through early 19th Century). With the rise of urban America, cities continued this tradition and began regulating firearms in a newly emerging public forum: the urban park.
We differ with the district court as to the conventionality and representativeness of the State's analogues as to firearm regulation in urban parks because the district court erroneously discounted many of the State's proffered analogues. Critically, the court failed to consider the medieval English law and Founding era laws.91 This initial error tainted the rest of the district court's analysis by obscuring that the later territorial and municipal laws, far from being outliers, were consistent with a “long, unbroken line of common-law” and Founding-era precedent. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 35, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Given the continuity of the tradition of regulating firearms in crowded public forums, there was no reason for the district court to discount territorial laws, municipal laws (insofar as the states in which the cities were located did not have identical state law counterparts), or laws from the late 19th century. Once situated within the line of the English, Founding-era, and Reconstruction state statues cited by the State, the territorial and municipal laws are exactly the opposite of the “few late-19thcentury outlier jurisdictions” offered and discounted in Bruen and should have been considered by the district court. Id. at 70, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
b. Consistency with Tradition
It is not enough for the State to point to well-established and representative analogues; the contemporary regulation it seeks to defend must also be “consistent” with the tradition established by those analogues. Id. at 34, 142 S.Ct. 2111. We now turn to this aspect of the inquiry.
Whether § 265.01-e’s prohibition on firearms in urban parks is consistent with this Nation's tradition is a straightforward inquiry. It is obvious that § 265.01-e burdens Second Amendment rights in a distinctly similar way (i.e., by prohibiting carriage) and for a distinctly similar reason (i.e., maintaining order in often-crowded public squares) as do the plethora of regulations provided by the State, many of which specifically applied to urban public parks. This demonstrates § 265.01-e’s consistency with the Second Amendment.92 See Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1901 (“This provision is ‘relevantly similar’ to those founding era regimes in both why and how it burdens the Second Amendment right.” (quoting Bruen, 597 U.S. at 29, 142 S.Ct. 2111)).
We are unconvinced by the Plaintiffs’ argument that the former use of Boston Common and similar spaces as gathering grounds for the militia undermines a tradition of regulating firearms in urban public parks. Though Plaintiffs urge that Boston Common was the Nation's first urban public park, it appears to have gained that distinction only in retrospect. “The modern idea of the park emerged in the nineteenth century,” before which “open spaces that were not privately owned ․ consisted of grazing areas open to all,” with Boston Common being the “most famous example for this kind of [grazing] park space.” Nadav Shoked, Property Law's Search for a Public, 97 Wash. U. L. Rev. 1517, 1556–57 (2020); see also Address of L. E. Holden, Cleveland, O., Bulletin of the American Park and Outdoor Association 3 (Volume 5 Rep. of the Am. Park and Outdoor Art Ass'n, June 1901), available at rb.gy/0flfx [https://perma.cc/FCU7-V2JW] (noting that at Boston Common's origin in 1633 there “was little if any idea that it would ever be a park ․ [i]t was kept and occupied as a common till a very recent date, and it was not until 1859 that the question was finally settled ․ that Boston Common should be a public park”). Moreover, the use of the Boston Common for organized and disciplined militia exercises and mustering hardly supports the notion that public recreational parks (to the extent the Common can be so characterized) were considered appropriate places for ordinary citizens to be armed outside the context of such military purposes. Thus, though the history of firearm regulation in the 17th-century Boston Common might tell us about the national tradition of regulating firearms in militia mustering grounds and “grazing areas open to all,” it tells us little about the history of firearm regulation in the public square.
The district court committed this same analogical error when it faulted the State for failing to produce historical statutes “banning the carrying of guns from older-named places such as ‘commons’ or ‘greens.’ ” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 325 (emphasis omitted). To today's minds, commons, greens, and public parks may seem alike; but, as we have just described, our 18th century forebears would have considered commons and greens to be public grazing areas and not places of social recreation. See Shoked, supra, at 1556–57. Accordingly, though commons, greens, and public parks “are relevantly similar” if one's metric is green spaces in cities, they are not relevantly similar if the “applicable metric” is gun regulation in spaces that, like urban parks do today, have historically acted as public forums and places of social recreation. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 29, 142 S.Ct. 2111; see also id. (“[B]ecause ‘everything is similar in infinite ways to everything else,’ one needs ‘some metric enabling the analogizer to assess which similarities are important and which are not[.]’ ” (first quoting Cass Sunstein, supra, at 773, 130 S.Ct. 3020; then quoting F. Schauer & B. Spellman, supra, at 254) (alterations adopted and internal citations omitted)).
The State's justification for § 265.01-e appears to be the same for rural as for urban parks, even though rural parks much more resemble the commons of yore than the historical and often-crowded public squares, i.e., fairs, markets, and urban public parks, regulated under the State's historical analogues.93 Rural parks do not as neatly resemble quintessential public squares in that they are not primarily designed for peaceable assembly.
As opposed to fairs, markets, or the new, urban parks of the mid-19th century, i.e., quintessential and often-crowded public spaces, the more proper analogue for rural parks based on the record before us appears to be “commons” and “wilderness areas.” New York describes its Adirondack Park, which encompasses “one-third of the total land area of New York State,” as containing “vast forests, rolling farmlands, towns and villages, mountains and valleys, lakes, ponds and free-flowing rivers, private lands and public forest.” Parks, Recreation and Historic Prevention, Adirondack Region, New York State, available at https://parks.ny.gov/regions/adirondack/default.aspx [https://perma.cc/ZNZ2-Z97B]. This description echoes that of the “New England commons ․ spaces held by the community for shared utilitarian purposes,”94 much more than it does the “communal spaces”95 and “quintessential public space[s]”96 embodied by urban parks.
But we need not resolve this line-drawing issue on a facial challenge. Although we doubt that the evidence presently in the record could set forth a well-established tradition of prohibiting firearm carriage in rural parks, we are mindful that this litigation is still in its early stages and that the State did not distinguish between rural and urban parks in its arguments to this Court or below. All told, the State's proffered analogues, which set forth a well-established and representative tradition of firearm regulation in often-crowded public squares such as urban parks, are sufficient to survive a facial challenge.97 See Bonta, 594 U.S. at 615, 141 S.Ct. 2373 (To mount a successful facial challenge, the plaintiff “must ‘establish that no set of circumstances exists under which the [law] would be valid,’ or show that the law lacks ‘a plainly legitimate sweep.’ ” (first quoting Salerno, 481 U.S. at 745, 107 S.Ct. 2095; then quoting Wash. State Grange, 552 U.S. at 449, 128 S.Ct. 1184)).
* * *
As § 265.01-e(2)(d) applies to urban parks, the State has carried its burden by placing the regulation within a national tradition of regulating firearms in often-crowded public squares, including, specifically, city parks. Accordingly, we VACATE the district court's preliminary injunction as to § 265.01-e(2)(d).
3. Analysis of the Historical Analogues — Zoos
To defend § 265.01-e’s regulation of firearms in zoos, the State relies on two of the same analogical categories as for public parks: prohibiting firearms in crowded places and in places where children congregate. The State also points out that, contrary to the district court's assertion, nearly 70 percent of visitors to zoos are parties with children. See Visitor Demographics, Ass'n of Zoos and Aquariums, available at https://www.aza.org/partnerships-visitor-demographics[https://perma.cc/A6FH-W774].
a. Well-Established and Representative
For the reasons laid out in our discussion of public parks, the State's evidence demonstrates a well-established and representative tradition of regulating firearms in densely trafficked public forums. We rely on Bruen for the proposition that the tradition of regulating firearms in spaces frequented by children is also well-established and representative. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
b. Consistency with Tradition
Section 265.01-e’s firearm ban in zoos is consistent with the State's analogues that establish a history of regulating firearms in crowded places and locations frequented by children. Although zoos are relatively modern institutions,98 the Bruen analysis remains valid and useful, subject to the more “nuanced approach” announced in Bruen. 597 U.S. at 27, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
Given that 70 percent of zoo visitors come accompanied by children, the tradition of prohibiting firearms in places frequented by children straightforwardly supports the regulation of firearms in zoos. For its part, the history of regulating firearms in often-crowded public spaces supports the firearm restriction in zoos in two additional ways. First, the statutes adduced by the State prohibited firearms not only in crowded “public squares” such as fairs, markets, and 19th century urban parks, but also more generally in ballrooms and social gatherings. See J.A. 602 (1870 Tex Gen. Laws 63, ch. 46); 605–06 (1869 Tenn. Pub. Acts 23–24); 611 (1883 Mo. Sess. Laws 76); 617 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 17); 621 (1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, § 7). Accordingly, these laws indicate that a high population density in discrete, confined spaces, such as quintessential public squares, has historically justified firearm restrictions. State court cases from this era confirm as much. See, e.g., English, 35 Tex. at 478–79 (“it appears [ ] little short of ridiculous, that any one should claim the right to carry upon his person” a firearm into “a ball room, or any other place where ladies or gentleman are congregated together”). Second, these same laws support firearm restrictions because zoos are spaces that provide educational opportunities. See J.A. 602 (1870 Tex Gen. Laws 63, ch. 46); 605–06 (1869 Tenn. Pub. Acts 23–24); 611 (1883 Mo. Sess. Laws 76); 617 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 17); 621 (1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, § 7). That the same laws restricting firearms in public forums would also do so in spaces hosting educational and scientific opportunities makes sense. Both public squares and educational and scientific spaces inherently presume orderly and peaceable assembly.
Contrary to the district court's conclusion, the location of some zoos within public parks, and their consequent automatic coverage by those parks’ firearm regulations, does not cut against the State. The district court's conclusion was based on its erroneous notion that the zoos’ “enjoy[ment of] their surrounding parks’ protections ․ shows that zoos were in need of no more protection than the parks in which they were located.” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 327. But the State was under no burden to demonstrate that zoos are especially deserving of firearm regulation, only that such regulation is consistent with Second Amendment tradition. That zoos were unproblematically covered by the firearm regulations of their surrounding parks tends to show that our forebearers took no Second Amendment issue with the regulation of firearms at zoos.
Because the State has demonstrated that prohibiting firearms at zoos is consistent with the country's tradition of regulating firearms in places of educational and scientific opportunity, places heavily trafficked by children, and places that are densely crowded, we reverse the district court's order preliminarily enjoining New York from enforcing § 265.01-e in zoos.
* * *
For the reasons set forth above, we VACATE the district court's preliminary injunction enjoining enforcement of § 265.01-e(2)(d) as applied to zoos and public parks.
IV. Premises Licensed for Alcohol Consumption
Section 265.01-e(2)(o) prohibits possession of a firearm in “any establishment holding an active license for on-premise consumption [of alcoholic beverages] ․ where alcohol is consumed.” The State does not challenge the district court's determination that one or more Plaintiffs had standing to challenge this provision of the CCIA, and we see no impediment to standing. Accordingly, we proceed directly to reviewing the district court's holding that the State failed to place § 265.01-e(2)(o) within the Nation's history of firearm regulation and vacate the preliminary injunction.
A. District Court Decision
As with the other regulations at issue in this appeal, the district court first determined that the conduct proscribed by § 265.01-e(2)(o) was within the plain text of the Second Amendment and placed the burden on the State defendants to prove the regulation's consistency with our Nation's history and tradition. The State argued that § 265.01-e(2)(o) is aimed at reducing the threat of gun violence resulting from “intoxicated persons gathered in large groups in confined spaces,” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 331, and directed the district court to seven historical analogues: (1) an 1867 Kansas law prohibiting carriage by “any person under the influence of intoxicating drink”; (2) an 1881 Missouri law prohibiting the same; (3) an 1889 Wisconsin law prohibiting “any person in a state of intoxication to go armed with any pistol or revolver”; (4) an 1878 Mississippi law prohibiting sale of “any weapon” to “any ․ person intoxicated, knowing him to be ․ in a state of intoxication”; (5) an 1890 Oklahoma law barring carriage by a public officer “while under the influence of intoxicating drinks” and also barring firearms in “any ball room ․ social party or social gathering”; (6) an 1870 Texas law barring firearms in “a ball room, social party or other social gathering composed of ladies and gentlemen”; and (7) an 1889 Arizona law barring firearms in any “place where persons are assembled for amusement ․ or into a ball room, social party or social gathering.” Id. at 332.
The district court discounted the Oklahoma and Arizona statutes as coming from territories and the 1889 Wisconsin law as being too removed from either the Founding or Reconstruction. The district court then noted that the five remaining analogues appear “to have been aimed at denying the possession of guns to persons who were likely to pose a danger or disturbance to the public” and did so either by prohibiting carriage to those who were intoxicated or those who were likely to disturb a social party or gathering. Id. It then assumed, without deciding, that the five analogues it was considering were both sufficiently well-established and representative to constitute a tradition but held that the tradition established by those laws was not sufficiently analogous to justify § 265.01-e(2)(o).
In the district's court view, “[t]he problem” with § 265.01-e(2)(o) is that it “is not limited to persons who have been served and/or who are consuming alcohol,” nor “is it even limited to persons intoxicated in establishments,” but rather it “broadly prohibits concealed carry by license holders ․ who will be merely eating at the establishments.” Id. While the court “acknowledge[d] the historical support” in the State's analogues “for a law prohibiting becoming intoxicated while carrying a firearm,” it concluded that those analogues did not justify criminalizing “mere presence” at a liquor-licensed establishment. Id. at 333 (emphasis removed). This is because the State's historical analogues governed behavior, while § 265.01-e(2)(o) governs places. Meanwhile, the district court appears to have rejected the State's analogues prohibiting the carriage of firearms at social gatherings on the basis that the State had “adduce[d] no evidence of the approximate number of disturbances to ‘social gatherings’ at restaurants that were caused each year by those licensed individuals who carry concealed there.” Id. at 332.
B. The State's Historical Analogues
On appeal, the State relies largely on the same analogues as it did below to argue that § 265.01-e(2)(o) is in harmony with the tradition of regulating firearms in locations frequented by “concentrations of vulnerable or impaired people,” here intoxicated individuals, “who either cannot defend themselves or cannot be trusted to have firearms around them safely.” Nigrelli Br. at 62. The State also argues that the tradition of regulating firearms in “quintessentially crowded places,” which they argue liquor-licensed establishments generally are, supports § 265.01-e(2)(o).
As a preliminary matter, we address the district court's erroneous decision to afford little weight to the Arizona and Oklahoma statutes because they were territorial laws, and to the 1889 Wisconsin statute because of its distance from Reconstruction and the Founding.
As we have already explained, the district court's repeated and automatic rejection of any territorial laws and statutes from the latter half of the nineteenth century is not compelled by Bruen. True, Bruen counseled that evidence “that long predates either date may not illuminate the scope of the right if linguistic or legal conventions changed in the intervening years,” and that “[s]imilarly, we must also guard against giving postenactment history more weight than it can rightly bear.” 597 U.S. at 34–35, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (emphasis added). That observation, however, does not require courts to reflexively discount evidence from the latter half of the 19th century absent indications that such evidence is inconsistent with the national tradition. Likewise, the district court made too much of the fact that Bruen gave “little weight” to territorial laws. Id. at 69, 142 S.Ct. 2111. Not only did New York offer only one state law in support of its proper-cause requirement in Bruen, the territorial laws on which it relied in Bruen were “short lived” and some “were held unconstitutional shortly after passage,”99 while another “did not survive a Territory's admission to the Union as a State.” Id.
The circumstances leading to the Court's cautions in Bruen are not present here and did not require the district court to discount the territorial laws of Arizona and Oklahoma nor the 1889 Wisconsin law. Unlike in Bruen, there is no evidence in the record before us that the territorial laws were short-lived, did not survive admission to the Union, or were later held unconstitutional. Nor were these territorial laws aberrant to the national tradition. As discussed below, these territorial laws were consistent with five state laws already on the books when the territorial laws were enacted. Similarly, Wisconsin's 1889 law was not a late-term aberration from the national tradition, but an addition consistent with the older state laws from Kansas, Missouri, and Mississippi. All three statutes should have been considered by the district court.
1. Well-Established and Representative
We now hold what the district court assumed, that the State's historical analogues establish a consistent and representative tradition of regulating access to firearms by people with impaired self-control or judgment, specifically those who are intoxicated. Three of the State's analogues—the 1867 Kansas law, 1889 Wisconsin law, and 1883 Missouri law—prohibited intoxicated persons from carrying firearms. J.A. 691 (1867 Kan. Sess. Laws Ch. 12, p. 25) (“any person under the influence of intoxicating drink ․ who shall be found ․ carrying on his person a pistol ․ shall be subject to arrest”); id. at 694 (Wis. Stat. Ann. § 4379b (1889)) (“It shall be unlawful for any person in a state of intoxication to go armed with any pistol or revolver.”); id. at 611 (1883 Mo. Sess. Laws 76) (prohibiting carriage by any person “when intoxicated or under the influence of intoxicating drinks”). The State's three other analogues included a law that prohibited selling firearms to intoxicated persons, id. at 633 (1878 Miss. Laws 175); a law that required the keepers of “drinking saloon[s] to keep posted up in a conspicuous place in his bar room ․ a plain notice to travelers to divest themselves of their weapons,” id. at 617 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 17); and a law that prohibited carriage in “any place where intoxicating liquors are sold,” id. at 621 (1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, § 7). These six analogues, which applied to nine-and-a-half percent of Americans by 1889,100 establish a consistent and representative national tradition of regulating firearms due to the dangers posed by armed intoxicated individuals. This tradition was carried out in various forms: either by disarming intoxicated persons (as in Kansas, Wisconsin, and Missouri), prohibiting the sale of firearms to intoxicated persons (as in Mississippi), or prohibiting firearms in liquor-serving or -selling establishments (as in Arizona and Oklahoma).
In addition to these statutory analogues, the State points to the Missouri Supreme Court's holding in State v. Shelby that the state's prohibition of firearm carriage by intoxicated persons was in “perfect harmony with the constitution” given the “mischief to be apprehended from an intoxicated person going abroad with fire-arms.” 2 S.W. at 469; see also id. (noting that if the state could constitutionally regulate firearms in “time and place, ․ no good reason is seen why the legislature may not do the same thing with reference to the condition of the person who carries such weapons”). Thus, not only do the six statutory analogues indicate that the Nation's early legislatures understood prohibiting the carriage of firearms by intoxicated persons and in liquor-serving establishments to be constitutional, but at least one state court did so as well. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 68, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (explaining that state court decisions help today's courts understand “the basis” of a historical analogue's “perceived legality”).101
2. Consistency with Tradition
We now turn to whether § 265.01-e(2)(o) is consistent with the well-established and representative tradition established by the State's analogues. We hold that it is consistent with both analogical categories established by the State, as liquor-licensed establishments are both typically crowded milieus and are frequented by intoxicated individuals who cannot necessarily be trusted with firearms and who may also, due to their intoxication, be unable to defend themselves effectively.102
Both categories of analogues burdened Second Amendment rights in a similar manner and for similar reasons as § 265.01-e(2)(o). Contemporaneous state case law reveals that historical regulations prohibiting firearms at social gatherings, parties, and ball rooms were justified by the “duties and proprieties of social life.” Andrews, 50 Tenn. at 181–82; see id. at 170, 181–82 (upholding 1869 Tennessee statute that prohibited carriage at “fair[s], race course[s], or other public assembl[ies]”); see J.A. 605 (1869 Tenn. Pub. Acts 23). In a similar vein, the State explains that § 265.01-e(2)(o) is motivated by the need to protect those in crowded social spaces.
And, though the State does not explicitly refer to historical statutes regulating firearms in other crowded spaces such as fairs and markets, those too provide support for regulating firearms in crowded places and keeping such spaces peaceful, as we have already discussed, see supra Sensitive Locations § III.B. As to means, both § 265.01-e(2)(o) and its historical “crowded space” analogues achieve their purpose by prohibiting carriage in heavily-trafficked spaces. Likewise, contemporaneous state case law reveals that intoxicated-persons statutes were motivated by the need to disarm intoxicated individuals who could not be trusted with weapons. See Shelby, 2 S.W. at 469–70 (holding that the “mischief” posed by intoxicated persons carrying weapons justified a statute prohibiting as much). As we have noted, these statutes achieved their objective in various ways. Some did so by disarming intoxicated individuals themselves, others by prohibiting sale to intoxicated persons, and yet others by prohibiting firearms in liquor-serving or -selling establishments altogether. Section 265.01-e(2)(o), which operates by prohibiting firearms in liquor-serving establishments, is directly parallel to the latter historical statutes.
When paired with the crowded space analogues, even absent the historical statutes prohibiting carriage in liquor-serving establishments, the analogues prohibiting intoxicated persons from carrying or purchasing firearms justify § 265.01-e(2)(o). Whereas the crowded space analogues justify prohibiting firearms in heavily trafficked places, the intoxicated-persons analogues justify prohibiting firearms to intoxicated persons who cannot be trusted with weapons. Together, these statutes justify regulating firearms in crowded spaces in which intoxicated persons are likely present. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“[E]ven if a modern-day regulation is not a dead ringer for historical precursors, it still may be analogous enough to pass constitutional muster.”).
The district court made two errors in reaching its holding that § 265.01-e(2)(o) was inconsistent with the Nation's tradition. For one, as described above, it erroneously declined to consider the analogues from Arizona, Oklahoma, and Wisconsin. Like § 265.01-e(2)(o), the Arizona and Oklahoma statutes prohibited firearms carriage in establishments serving liquor. These analogues provide the (admittedly unnecessary) historical twins sought by the district court and demonstrate that regulating firearms based on liquor-serving places rather than intoxication is consistent with the national tradition.103 Yet, even putting aside the Arizona and Oklahoma statutes, the district court erred in rejecting the State's remaining behavior-based historical analogues in search of a place-based “historical twin.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (emphasis removed). For the reasons we describe above, § 265.01-e(2)(o) is “analogous enough” to the State's behavior-based and crowded location historical analogues to “pass constitutional muster.” Id.
* * *
For the aforementioned reasons we VACATE the district court's preliminary injunction enjoining enforcement of § 265.01-e(2)(o).
V. Theaters, Conference Centers, and Banquet Halls
N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-e(2)(p) is a wide-ranging ban on gun carriage in “any place used for the performance, art entertainment [sic], gaming, or sporting events” that provides a long list of examples of such locations. The district court enjoined enforcement of § 265.01-e(2)(p) with respect to three of those locations: “theaters,” “conference centers,” and “banquet halls.” We vacate that injunction, concluding (1) that no Plaintiff presented a justiciable challenge to the conference center and banquet hall provisions (and thus that the district court's injunction was entered without subject-matter jurisdiction), and (2) that Plaintiffs have not shown a likelihood that the ban on carrying guns in theaters violates the Second Amendment.
A. Justiciability
The district court concluded that plaintiff Alfred Terrille had standing with respect to both conference centers and banquet halls, and that plaintiff Joseph Mann also had standing with respect to banquet halls. We disagree on both scores.
We consider first Terrille's claim as to conference centers and banquet halls (there is no dispute that, as the district court found, Terrille has standing with respect to theaters). See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 286. His September 19, 2022, declaration averred that he “plan[s] to attend the ․ NEACA Polish Community Center Gun Show, to occur on October 8–9, 2022, in Albany,” and that he “intend[s] to carry [his] firearm” there. J.A. 191–92 (Terrille Decl. ¶ 16). The gun show's host—the Polish Community Center—“describes itself as a conference center, banquet hall & wedding venue,” id., an unchallenged self-description that we credit.
This declaration was likely sufficient to establish Terrille's standing initially. But “[t]o qualify as a case fit for federal-court adjudication, ‘an actual controversy must be extant at all stages of review, not merely at the time the complaint is filed.’ ” Arizonans for Off. Eng. v. Arizona, 520 U.S. 43, 67, 117 S.Ct. 1055, 137 L.Ed.2d 170 (1997) (quoting Preiser v. Newkirk, 422 U.S. 395, 401, 95 S.Ct. 2330, 45 L.Ed.2d 272 (1975)). “[I]t is not enough that a dispute was very much alive when suit was filed ․ The parties must continue to have a personal stake in the outcome of the lawsuit.” Lewis v. Cont'l Bank Corp., 494 U.S. 472, 477–78, 110 S.Ct. 1249, 108 L.Ed.2d 400 (1990) (internal quotation marks omitted). “When the plaintiff no longer has a legally cognizable interest in the outcome of the action, the case becomes moot and is no longer a ‘case’ or ‘controversy’ for the purposes of Article III.” Stagg, P.C. v. U.S. Dep't of State, 983 F.3d 589, 601 (2d Cir. 2020) (citing Already, LLC v. Nike, Inc., 568 U.S. 85, 91, 133 S.Ct. 721, 184 L.Ed.2d 553 (2013)). “The question of standing bears close affinity to the question of mootness, which is whether the occasion for judicial intervention persists.” Chevron Corp. v. Donziger, 833 F.3d 74, 123 (2d Cir. 2016) (emphasis in original) (internal quotation marks omitted).
Even though Terrille likely had standing at the outset of this suit, his claim has become moot. Terrille's alleged injury-in-fact was a threatened prosecution for carrying a gun at a specific conference center/banquet hall on a specific date. But October 8–9 came and went, and there is no record as to whether the gun show took place, let alone whether Terrille attended it while armed.104 A past but unfulfilled intention to violate the law does not support pre-enforcement standing, and nothing in the record here (or in district court, see Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 286 n.52) shows that Terrille followed through on his intention to violate § 265.01-e(2)(p) in October 2022.
Nor did Terrille allege a future intention to visit a banquet hall or conference center while armed—for a gun show or otherwise. Plaintiffs claim that it is “evident from Terrille's affidavit that he regularly attends gun shows, which occur on a routine basis,”105 Appellee Nigrelli Br. at 9 (emphasis removed), but that is not so. Terrille discussed his plans to attend conference centers and banquet halls solely by reference to his desire to attend a specific gun show, and did so in a short and discrete section of his declaration (set out in the margin).106 We do not see in that averment—or anywhere else, e.g., J.A. 69 (Compl. ¶ 173)—the supposedly “evident” indicia that Terrille regularly visits banquet halls or conference centers while armed. In contrast, Plaintiff Johnson makes precisely such an assertion in discussing his interest in zoos, by stating that his and his wife's plans to visit the zoo in the coming fall is part of their regular practice of visiting the zoo “at least once or twice every fall.” J.A. 139–40 (Johnson Decl. ¶ 17).
Perhaps Plaintiffs ask us to construe Terrille's declaration generously and to infer from his stated intention to go to this gun show at a conference center/banquet hall while armed an unstated intention to attend other, future gun shows at conference centers/banquet halls while armed. But without more, such an inference is not logically sound. A person with a ticket to a play next week is not necessarily a regular theatergoer. Terrille could have alleged something more—a longstanding interest in and habit of attending gun shows, perhaps—but he did not, and we will not rewrite his declaration for him: As we have previously noted, “ ‘a live controversy is not maintained by speculation’ that the party might in the future be prevented from conducting an activity that it ‘currently asserts no plan to [conduct].’ ” Connecticut Citizens Def. League, Inc. v. Lamont, 6 F.4th 439, 445 (2d Cir. 2021) (brackets in original) (quoting City News & Novelty, Inc. v. City of Waukesha, 531 U.S. 278, 285, 121 S.Ct. 743, 148 L.Ed.2d 757 (2001)).
Furthermore, “[o]ur sensitivity to [justiciability] concerns is particularly acute when a litigant invokes the power of judicial review, a power at once justified and limited by our obligation to decide cases.” Frank v. United States, 78 F.3d 815, 832 (2d Cir. 1996), vacated, 521 U.S. 1114, 117 S.Ct. 2501, 138 L.Ed.2d 1007 (1997), relevant portion readopted, 129 F.3d 273, 275 (2d Cir. 1997); see also Raines v. Byrd, 521 U.S. 811, 819–20, 117 S.Ct. 2312, 138 L.Ed.2d 849 (1997) (The “standing inquiry has been especially rigorous when reaching the merits of the dispute would force us to decide whether an action taken by one of the other two branches of the Federal Government was unconstitutional.”). Though a request for judicial review does not actually modify the requirements for justiciability, we reiterate that a court must be confident that it is deciding a true “case or controversy”—rather than issuing an advisory opinion—when asked to invalidate the action of a co-ordinate branch or of a state. In such circumstances, courts should be reluctant to draw tenuous inferences from sparse declarations.
Plaintiffs make two further mootness arguments. First, they argue that any uncertainty as to what Terrille did on October 8th and 9th is the State's fault for declining to cross-examine Terrille at the evidentiary hearing in the district court. But it was not the State's job to adduce facts to sustain Terrille's injury. Plaintiffs also argue that Terrille should not be required to confess to the felony of going armed to a conference center. True, he “is not required to [confess to a crime] in order to establish standing.” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 290; accord Driehaus, 573 U.S. at 163, 134 S.Ct. 2334. But that was not his only option. If Terrille had averred that he wishes to attend gun shows (or other events) at conference centers or banquet halls while armed, with sufficient indicia to permit a plausible inference of future violations of this law, jurisdiction might have been proper. Or Terrille could have asserted that he wanted to attend other gun shows while armed but was deterred from doing so by the CCIA. But he did neither.
We are mindful that a plaintiff may fall between stools: allege future conduct too imminent and the claim will become moot, but allege a generic or distant intention and the injury will be insufficiently specific. But as we have explained elsewhere in this opinion, it is simply not all that hard to allege a plausible “intention to engage in a course of conduct arguably affected with a constitutional interest,” Driehaus, 573 U.S. at 159, 134 S.Ct. 2334 (quoting Babbitt, 442 U.S. at 159, 99 S.Ct. 2213). The Supreme Court has repeatedly found plausible allegations of injury based on relatively vague future intentions. See supra Sensitive Locations § III.A. A gun owner who alleges a prior visit to a venue, a reason or wish to visit again, and either a plan to do so (thereby subjecting himself to arrest) or a decision to forgo doing so for fear of prosecution will likely have adequately pled standing to seek a pre-enforcement injunction.107
Not so a plaintiff who alleges only a single occasion on which he intends to violate the challenged law and then fails to indicate that he followed through, that he was dissuaded by legal prohibition, or that past practice predicts a violation in the future. Since Terrille has done none of the above, it is insufficiently clear that the injunction he seeks with respect to banquet halls and conference centers would affect him in any way. He has not demonstrated an ongoing stake in the outcome of the litigation; his claim is—and was at the time the district court issued its injunction—moot. Cf. Palmer v. Amazon.com, Inc., 51 F.4th 491, 503 (2d Cir. 2022) (“A case becomes moot when it is impossible for a court to grant any effectual relief whatever to the prevailing party.” (quoting Lamont, 6 F.4th at 444)). And since Terrille was the only plaintiff found to have standing with respect to conference centers, we vacate that component of the district court's injunction as having been entered without jurisdiction.
The district court also concluded that Joseph Mann had standing to challenge the CCIA's prohibition on possessing a gun in banquet halls. Mann's declaration averred that his church “additionally [is] a ‘banquet hall’ as [parishioners] often break bread together.” J.A. 183 (Mann Decl. ¶ 34). The district court accepted Mann's characterization and found that, given Mann's stated intention to carry a gun at the church, he had established injury-in-fact. See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 387.108 We disagree. Notwithstanding that people “break bread together” there, a church is not even arguably a “banquet hall” within the meaning of § 265.01-e(2)(p).
The Plaintiffs’ interpretation of “banquet hall” does not comport with ordinary meaning. See Manning v. Barr, 954 F.3d 477, 482 (2d Cir. 2020) (“[W]ords will be interpreted as taking their ordinary, contemporary, common meaning.” (quoting Arriaga v. Mukasey, 521 F.3d 219, 225 (2d Cir. 2008))). Just as “banquet” is not a synonym for “meal,”109 a “banquet hall” is not any place people eat together.110 Instead, the phrase ordinarily refers more specifically to a commercial space made available for special events: weddings, reunions, fundraisers, etc. Plaintiffs’ expansive definition of “banquet hall” would include a cafe, picnic tables in the park, or the dining room of a private residence.
Our intuitive understanding is confirmed by an examination of the company the phrase keeps. See, e.g., Homaidan v. Sallie Mae, Inc., 3 F.4th 595, 604 (2d Cir. 2021) (“[Noscitur a sociis] counsels that a word is given more precise content by the neighboring words with which it is associated.” (quoting Freeman v. Quicken Loans, Inc., 566 U.S. 624, 634–35, 132 S.Ct. 2034, 182 L.Ed.2d 955 (2012))). As used in paragraph (2)(p), “banquet hall” is only an example of a “place used for the performance, art entertainment [sic], gaming, or sporting events.” A church—even one hosting collective bread-breaking—is not such a place. The other listed examples immediately preceding “banquet halls” in § 265.01-e(2)(p), such as theaters, stadiums, concerts, amusement parks, and racetracks, further confirm our understanding of the term. Context thus tells us that the legislature could hardly have intended for “banquet hall” to cover all sites of group meals, including churches.
For these reasons, we conclude that Mann's proffered interpretation of the statute is not “reasonable enough” that he “may legitimately fear that [he] will face enforcement of the statute.” Picard, 42 F.4th at 98 (quoting Pac. Cap. Bank, 542 F.3d at 350). He has therefore not alleged an intention to engage in conduct which is “arguably proscribed by the law” he challenges, Driehaus, 573 U.S. at 162, 134 S.Ct. 2334 (internal quotation marks omitted), and has failed to establish injury-in-fact with respect to § 265.01-e(2)(p)’s application to banquet halls. Given the mootness of Terrille's challenge to the banquet hall provision, the district court lacked jurisdiction to enjoin enforcement of § 265.01-e(2)(p) with respect to banquet halls, and we vacate for that reason.
The State, on the other hand, does not challenge the district court's finding that Plaintiffs Terrille, Mann, and Johnson had standing as to theaters, and we see no impediment to standing. Accordingly, we now turn to the merits of the district court's preliminary injunction of § 265.01-e(2)(p) as applied to theaters.
B. Merits
1. District Court Decision
The State once again bore the burden of proving that § 265.01-e(2)(p), the purpose of which is to reduce the threat of gun violence toward large groups in confined locations, was consistent with the national tradition. To carry this burden, the State offered five analogues below, all of which we have already seen: (1) a 1786 Virginia law barring persons from “go[ing] [ ]or rid[ing] armed” in “fairs or markets, or in other places, in terror of the county”; (2) an 1869 Tennessee law barring carriage in “any fair, race course, or other public assembly of the people”; (3) an 1870 Texas law barring carriage in “a ball room, social party or other social gathering composed of ladies and gentleman”; (4) an 1889 Arizona law and (5) an 1890 Oklahoma law, both of which prohibited carriage in “any places where persons are assembled for amusement ․ or into any circus, show or public exhibition of any kind, or into a ball room, social party or social gathering.” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 333.
As it did elsewhere, the district court discounted the Oklahoma and Arizona statutes as coming from territories and the latter half of the 19th century. So, it considered only the first three analogues. These laws, determined the court, “appear to have been aimed at denying the possession of guns to persons who were likely to pose a danger or disturbance to the public.” Id at 334. Per the district court, they did so by denying firearms to persons who were either “riding in terror of the county” or “likely to disturb those attending a gathering of people (usually but not always outdoors) containing a dense population.” Id.
The district court concluded that neither set of analogues sustained the State's burden. Virginia's law prohibiting “riding in terror” was not on point because its regulation of “horseback-riding terrorists through fairs or markets” was not analogous to the “modern need to regulate law-abiding New York State citizens” wishing to carry concealed firearms. Id. (alterations adopted and internal quotation marks omitted). And whereas the “horseback riders referenced in the Virginia law were, by definition, brandishing arms and not carrying them concealed,” noted the court, “the modern regulation is not limited to instances in which the concealed carry licensees are ‘terrorizing’ others.” Id. Nor did the remaining two laws—the 1869 Tennessee and 1870 Texas statutes—carry the State's burden because those laws, by virtue of the relatively small portion of the American population they covered, were neither representative nor established. Yet, even assuming these statutes were representative and established, the district court refused to accept that these two statutes were analogous because the State had not demonstrated “that the modern need for this regulation is comparable to the need for its purported historical analogues” given the CCIA's licensing requirements. Id. at 335.
Having determined that none of the State's offered analogues carried its burden of placing § 265.01-e(2)(p) within the Nation's history of firearm regulation, the district court enjoined its enforcement.
2. The State's Historical Analogues
On appeal, the State argues that § 265.01-e(2)(p) is consistent with the Nation's tradition of regulating firearms in quintessentially crowded social places. As we have already laid out, above see Sensitive Locations Parts III.B.2 & IV.B.2, the State points to the following analogues to establish a tradition of crowded-place regulations: (1) a 1382 British statute forbidding going or riding “armed by night [ ]or by day, in fairs, markets,” Statute of Northampton 1328, 2 Edw. 3 c.3 (Eng.); (2) a 1792 North Carolina statute replicating the 1328 British statute and prohibiting firearms in fairs or markets, Collection of Statutes of the Parliament of England in Force in the State of North Carolina, pp. 60–61, ch. 3 (F. Martin Ed. 1792); (3) a 1786 Virginia law prohibiting “go[ing] [ ]or rid[ing] armed by night [ ]or by day, in fairs or markets, or in other places, in terror of the county,” J.A. 670 (1786 Va. Acts 35, ch. 49); (4) laws from 1869 Tennessee, 1870 Texas, 1883 Missouri, 1889 Arizona, and 1890 Oklahoma prohibiting firearms in crowded places such as assemblies for “educational, literary or scientific purposes, or into a ball room, social party or social gathering,” J.A. 602 (1870 Tex. Gen. Laws 63, ch. 46);111 and (5) Missouri, Tennessee, and Texas state court opinions upholding those states’ regulations as constitutional, see Shelby, 2 S.W. at 469; English, 35 Tex. at 478–79; Andrews, 50 Tenn. at 182. Plaintiffs cite, and we have found, no successful legal challenges to any of these analogues, or any evidence that they were ever politically controversial.
We have already held that the above analogues set forth both a well-established and representative tradition of regulating firearms in quintessentially crowded places, see above Sensitive Locations § III.B.2.a. The question to which we turn, therefore, is whether § 265.01-e(2)(p) is consistent with that tradition, see above Sensitive Locations § III.B.2.b. We hold that it is and, accordingly, vacate the preliminary injunction.
The State's proffered analogues set forth a tradition of regulating firearms in quintessentially crowded places, particularly those spaces that are (1) discrete in the sense that they contain crowds in physically delineated or enclosed spaces, e.g., circuses, ball rooms, fairs, and markets, and (2) “where persons are assembled for amusement,” J.A. 617 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 17), or for “educational [or] literary purposes,” id. at 602 (1870 Tex. Gen. Laws 63, ch. 46). We need not stretch the analogy far to see that § 265.01-e(2)(p) is consistent with this tradition in both senses. It regulates firearms in discrete, densely crowded physical spaces wherein people assemble for amusement, educational, or literary purposes, which fairly describes theaters.112
The district court failed to properly appreciate the national tradition of which § 265.01-e(2)(p) is a part for several reasons.
First, the court improperly discounted the Oklahoma and Arizona statutes based on their origins as territorial laws from the late 19th Century. Second, it improperly discounted the laws from Tennessee and Texas based on those states’ populations relative to that of the Nation at the time.113 For the reasons we have already described, see above Sensitive Locations § III.B.2, this was error.
Third, the court dismissed the 1786 Virginia law prohibiting “go[ing] [ ]or rid[ing] armed by night nor by day, in fairs or markets, or in other places, in terror of the county,” J.A. at 670 (1786 Va. Acts 35, ch. 49), as insufficiently analogous because the Virginia law was aimed at “terrorists” and not the type of lawful gun-owners covered by § 265.01-e(2)(p). Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 338–39. Even if we accept that the Virginia law was solely aimed at people who terrorize, the district court failed to appreciate that the Founding-era North Carolina statute prohibited firearms in fairs and markets with no reference to terroristic conduct.114 It also failed to consider that the tradition beginning with the Virginia and North Carolina laws evolved over the years between the Founding and Reconstruction toward the North Carolina model, i.e., to prohibit firearms in quintessentially crowded places absolutely, without reference to behavior. See, e.g., statutes cited above note 82. Thus, in the context of regulating firearms in discrete, crowded places, the Virginia law's “terroristic” conduct requirement is the outlier among the national tradition.115 In any event, even without the Virginia law, the State's remaining historical analogues, and state case law finding three of those analogues constitutional, are enough.
Fourth, the district court improperly dismissed the remaining two analogues it did consider—the statutes from Tennessee and Texas—because the State failed to show that the need for gun-regulation in crowded places today is comparable to the need for such traditional regulations in the past given the CCIA's extensive background check requirements. But that was not the State's burden.116 The State's burden was to prove that § 265.01-e(2)(p) is consistent with a national tradition. It did so.
* * *
For the aforementioned reasons, the order of the district court preliminarily enjoining the State from enforcing § 265.01-e(2)(p) is VACATED.
VI. First Amendment Gatherings
Section 265.01-e(2)(s) makes it a crime to possess a gun at “any gathering of individuals to collectively express their constitutional rights to protest or assemble.” The district court found that Plaintiffs Terrille and Mann both had standing to challenge this restriction. The State has not argued otherwise, but “it is well established that the court has an independent obligation to assure that standing exists, regardless of whether it is challenged by any of the parties.” Summers v. Earth Island Inst., 555 U.S. 488, 499, 129 S.Ct. 1142, 173 L.Ed.2d 1 (2009); accord In re Clinton Nurseries, Inc., 53 F.4th 15, 22 (2d Cir. 2022). Fulfilling that obligation here, we conclude that neither Terrille nor Mann has presented justiciable constitutional challenges to paragraph (2)(s).
A. Mann
The district court concluded that Mann has standing because paragraph (2)(s) applies to Sunday worship at Mann's church—“expressive religious assemblies,” in the district court's words. Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 291. Since Mann intends to carry a gun during worship services, the district court found that Mann had alleged a credible threat of prosecution for violating paragraph (2)(s). Id.; see also J.A. 182 (Mann Decl. ¶ 32). However, as a matter of statutory interpretation, neither a worship service nor other “expressive religious assemblies” are even arguably covered by paragraph (2)(s).
The inquiry depends on the provision's purpose: guns are banned only when people gather “to collectively express their constitutional rights to protest or assemble.” It is unreasonable to interpret this text to include every gathering or even every “expressive gathering.” For one thing, that would render wholly superfluous § 265.01-e(2)(c), which specifically prohibits guns in “any place of worship.” Other portions of § 265.01-e would also be swallowed by paragraph (2)(s). “Theaters” and “performance venues”—included in paragraph (2)(p)—do little else but host gatherings involving expression. Likewise, many events hosted at “exhibits, conference centers, [and] banquet halls” can be categorized as “expressive gatherings.” See N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-e(2)(p). The CCIA may be broad, but we will not read it to be redundant.
Paragraph (2)(s)’s placement within § 265.01-e confirms that it was aimed at protests and other demonstrations rather than at an undifferentiated category of gatherings that would include worship services. Within § 265.01-e(2), related sensitive locations tend to be grouped together: childcare and other youth programs appear back-to-back with “nursery schools, preschools, and summer camps,” N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-e(2)(e)–(f); and programs for the vulnerable—persons suffering from addiction, mental illness, poverty, disability, and homelessness—all appear in sequence, see id. §§ 265.01-e(2)(g)–(k). It is thus probative that paragraph (2)(s) immediately follows a ban on guns at:
any public sidewalk or other public area restricted from general public access for a limited time or special event that has been issued a permit for such time or event by a governmental entity, or subject to specific, heightened law enforcement protection ․
Id. § 256.01-e(2)(r). This pattern of grouping by affinity suggests that subparagraph (s) deals with “assemblies” similar to those on a sidewalk or on a road closed by police.
Although some court decisions have suggested broad First Amendment protection for “assemblies,” see Coates v. City of Cincinnati, 402 U.S. 611, 615, 91 S.Ct. 1686, 29 L.Ed.2d 214 (1971) (suggesting a First Amendment right to “gather in public places for social or political purposes”); De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U.S. 353, 365, 57 S.Ct. 255, 81 L.Ed. 278 (1937) (stating that “peaceable assembly for lawful discussion cannot be made a crime” in part because of the Assembly Clause), the “constitutional right to assemble” is more usually discussed as being “cognate to those of free speech and free press,” De Jonge, 299 U.S. at 364, 57 S.Ct. 255, and “intimately connected both in origin and in purpose[ ] with the other First Amendment rights of free speech and free press,” United Mine Workers of Am., Dist. 12 v. Illinois State Bar Ass'n, 389 U.S. 217, 222, 88 S.Ct. 353, 19 L.Ed.2d 426 (1967).
And the legislature's pairing of “assembl[y]” with “protest” in § 265.01-e(2)(s) strongly suggests that the legislature was concerned with protest-type demonstrations rather than attempting to reach any assembly conceivably protected by the First Amendment. Cf. McDonnell v. United States, 579 U.S. 550, 569, 136 S.Ct. 2355, 195 L.Ed.2d 639 (2016) (“[Noscitur a sociis] is often wisely applied where a word is capable of many meanings in order to avoid the giving of unintended breadth to the Acts of Congress.” (quoting Jarecki v. G.D Searle & Co., 367 U.S. 303, 307, 81 S.Ct. 1579, 6 L.Ed.2d 859 (1961))). It is implausible that the New York legislature meant for paragraph (2)(s) to apply wherever people gather for social or political purposes (which is everywhere), or whenever people engage in lawful discussion (which is all the time). It is highly unlikely that the legislature would slip in a prohibition of such sprawling breadth as one of many entries in an enumeration of twenty sensitive locations. Such a sweeping bar would also offend the Supreme Court's admonition against “expanding the category of ‘sensitive places’ simply to all places of public congregation that are not isolated from law enforcement.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 31, 142 S.Ct. 2111. The CCIA is in conversation with Bruen: the legislature may have overreached in certain respects, but the general point was to revise New York's gun laws to withstand Bruen, not to attempt exactly what it forbade.
Moreover, it is easy to infer what the legislature had in mind. Peaceful demonstrations petitioning the government to take or desist from particular actions are a vital part of democratic discourse; demonstrations by armed mobs are something else. Similarly, counter-demonstrations often lead to dangerous confrontations; how much more so if a peaceful protest is met by counter-demonstrators who are armed. It is thus reasonable to assume that the legislature was concerned that carrying firearms in connection with such protests conveys intimidation rather than free expression, a concern that would not extend to ordinary religious or social gatherings at which people exercise their rights to gather and speak with each other.
Accordingly, we conclude that worship services at Mann's church are not arguably “gathering[s] of individuals to collectively express their constitutional rights to protest or assemble” and that he has thus not alleged injury-in-fact with respect to § 265.01-e(2)(s).
B. Terrille
The district court found that Alfred Terrille had standing to challenge the constitutionality of paragraph (2)(s) based on his intention to attend the Polish Community Center Gun Show on October 8–9, 2022. But for the reasons explained above with respect to conference centers and banquet halls, Terrille's failure to demonstrate that he attended the gun show while armed, was dissuaded by law from doing so, or intends to attend another gun show in the future means that Terrille's challenge to paragraph (2)(s) is now moot.
Moreover, a gun show is not arguably a “gathering of individuals to collectively express their constitutional rights to protest or assemble” under paragraph (2)(s). Though Terrille states that “one of [his] main reasons for attending [the Polish Community Center Gun Show], and a huge part of any gun show, is the conversations with fellow gun owners, which invariably includes discussion of New York State's tyrannical gun laws,” J.A. 191–92 (Terrille Decl. ¶ 16), that does not on its own bring a gun show within paragraph (2)(s). A gun show is a commercial exhibition: that attendees might also engage in speech, including on politically-charged topics, does not make it a gathering for the purpose of expressing participants’ “constitutional right to protest or assemble.” As discussed, the challenged law does not cover every gathering where expression might occur. A book fair is not a qualifying gathering even if attendees anticipate conversations about censorship. So, even if Terrille's claim was not moot, it still would not be justiciable.
* * *
Since neither Mann nor Terrille present justiciable challenges § 265.01-e(2)(s), the district court was without jurisdiction to enjoin its enforcement.117 We accordingly VACATE that portion of the district court's preliminary injunction.
RESTRICTED LOCATIONS
Under § 265.01-d of the CCIA, a “person is guilty of criminal possession of a weapon in a restricted location when such person possesses a firearm, rifle, or shotgun and enters into or remains on or in private property where such person knows or reasonably should know that the owner or lessee of such property has not permitted such possession by clear and conspicuous signage indicating that the carrying of firearms, rifles, or shotguns on their property is permitted or by otherwise giving express consent.” The effect of this “restricted location” provision is to create a default presumption that carriage on any private property is unlawful —whether property is open or closed to the public—unless the property owner has indicated by “clear and conspicuous signage” or express verbal consent that carriage is allowed.118
As discussed above, the Plaintiffs moved to preliminarily enjoin enforcement of the restricted locations provision. Specifically, all six Plaintiffs challenged the provision as violative of the First Amendment and Second Amendment. After finding that each of these Plaintiffs had standing to challenge this provision, the district court enjoined the restricted-locations provision in its entirety on both First Amendment compelled speech and Second Amendment grounds. See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 294, 339–47.
I. Standing
In assessing standing, we need only consider the Second Amendment challenge. The State argues that none of the Plaintiffs has standing to bring a Second Amendment challenge to § 265.01-d. “[A]n injunction against defendants cannot vindicate plaintiffs’ asserted desire to carry guns onto others’ property,” the State contends, because that “inability ․ would flow not from defendants’ enforcement of the CCIA, but rather from decisions by property owners or lessees about whether to allow guns on the premises.” Nigrelli Br. at 70.
We disagree. Whether or not a property owner or lessee has decided to allow guns on their premises, the relevant injury for standing purposes is the credible threat of arrest and prosecution that Plaintiffs face if they do so without first receiving permission for armed entry, as they claim a right (and willingness) to do. See, e.g., J.A. 140–41 (Johnson Decl. ¶¶ 18–21). Under § 265.01-d, an armed entry without explicit prior permission would be prosecutable even if the property owner or lessee later discovers the entrant is armed and consents to his carriage. And that injury is clearly redressable by an injunction against enforcement of the private-property restriction. Further, although the State contends that this injury is not traceable to the State (and thus not redressable) because Plaintiffs’ exclusion occurs due to a decision by a third-party to deny consent, that argument ignores the provision's criminally enforceable presumption against carriage. In other words, absent § 265.01-d, a licensed gun owner could bring his concealed firearm into, for example, a privately owned department store if the store owner did not clearly communicate to the public (or to the gun owner directly) any position on whether guns were permitted, but the passage of the law makes carrying a licensed gun into that store a crime even though no such prohibition had been posted or communicated. That change in the gun licensee's rights is affected by the statute, not by any action of the private property owner. Accordingly, Plaintiffs have standing to challenge § 265.01-d as violating the Second Amendment.
II. Merits
A. The District Court Decision
The district court began its analysis of the restricted location provision by noting that the provision applies both to “all privately owned property that is not open to the public (and that is not a ‘sensitive location’ under Section 4 of the CCIA)” as well as to “all privately owned property that is open for business to the public (and that is not a ‘sensitive location’ under Section 4 of the CCIA).” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 339. The court focused its analysis on those restricted locations open to the public, concluded that the CCIA's restriction of firearms in such locations “finds little historical precedent,” id. at 340, and enjoined enforcement.
The district court rejected the State's eight proffered analogues, of which six were state laws ranging from the early 18th-century to late 19th-century that prohibited carrying firearms onto private property for the purpose of hunting game. Id. at 340-41. The remaining two proffered statutes, a 1771 New Jersey statute and an 1865 Louisiana statute, prohibited the carriage of firearms generally on private property without the owner's consent.
The court found that the six “anti-poaching” statutes were inapposite. They were “aimed at preventing hunters (sometimes only hunters who are convicted criminals) from taking game off of other people's lands (usually enclosed) without the owner's permission.” Id at 340. Barring “some people from openly carrying rifles on other people's farms and lands in 19th century America,” concluded the court, “is hardly analogous to barring all license holders from carrying concealed handguns in virtually every commercial building now.” Id. at 341. Moreover, the anti-poaching statutes served a specific purpose distinct from the concerns animating § 265.01-d. According to the district court, “poaching was a specific and pernicious problem” in each of the six states with anti-poaching laws, whereas § 265.01-d is aimed at “ensu[ring] that property owners and lessees can make informed decision.” Id. (internal quotation marks omitted). In sum, the court concluded that the need to restrict poaching “appears of little comparable analogousness to the need to restrict law-abiding responsible license holders in establishments that are open for business to the public today.” Id.
The district court also rejected the State's remaining analogues—the 1771 New Jersey and 1865 Louisiana laws. Even assuming, arguendo, that they were well-established, the court found that they were not representative, given that the populations of New Jersey and Louisiana together was 4.2 percent of the Nation at that time.
As to § 265.01-d’s firearm restrictions on private property closed to the public, the district court agreed with the State. With no merits analysis, the court was persuaded “that the Second Amendment is not the best place to look for protection” of carriage rights on property closed to the public because “thus far the Second Amendment has been found to protect the right to keep and bear arms for self-defense only in one's own home or in public.” Id. at 343. Having concluded that regulations of firearms on private property closed to the public are outside the scope of the Second Amendment, the court did not analyze this aspect of the regulation under Bruen.
Following its analysis of the Plaintiffs’ First Amendment challenge to the restricted locations provision, the district court enjoined § 265.01-d in all of its applications, i.e., as applied to private property that is both open and closed to the public. Importantly, the district court explained that “even if its First Amendment analysis were flawed,” the Second Amendment grounds alone were sufficient to “preliminary enjoin all of” § 265.01-d. Id. at 347. As discussed below, that was error.
B. Merits Analysis
1. Scope of Second Amendment
At the outset, to the extent the restricted location provision applies to private property open to the public, the regulated conduct falls within the Second Amendment right to carry firearms in self-defense outside the home. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 33, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“the Second Amendment guarantees a general right to public carry”). Otherwise, because over 91 percent of land in New York state is privately held, the restricted location provision would turn much of the state of New York into a default no-carriage zone. 119 We need not and do not decide, however, whether the Second Amendment includes a right to carry on private property not open to the public. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 31, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (explaining that though there is a general right to public carriage “we ‘do not undertake an exhaustive historical analysis of the full scope of the Second Amendment’ ” (ellipses omitted) (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783)).
On appeal, the State argues that because the district court failed to consider whether there is a Second Amendment right to carry firearms on private property not open to the public, it short-circuited the first step of the analysis and thus erroneously put the burden on the State to establish § 265.01-d’s consistency with the national tradition.120 But the district court addressed the Second Amendment challenge to the restricted location provision only insofar as it applies to private property open to the public.121 Indeed, with regard to property not open to the public, the court concluded that “the Second Amendment is not the best place to look for protection from that restriction, because thus far the Second Amendment has been found to protect the right to keep and bear arms for self-defense only in one's own home or in public.” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 343. Thus, the district court did not put the State to the burden of establishing § 265.01-d’s consistency with the national tradition, as that provision relates to property that is not open to the public.
Because the conduct regulated by § 265.01-d as it applies to private property that is open to the public is within the plain text of the Second Amendment, the district court permissibly proceeded to analyze whether § 265.01-d, as it applies to such property, is consistent with a well-established and representative national tradition. We now turn to that analysis.
2. The State's Analogues on Appeal
The State relies on the same analogues here as it did in the district court: (1) the 1715 Maryland law barring people “convicted of [certain crimes] ․ or ․ of evil fame, or any vagrant, or dissolute liver,” from “shoot[ing], kill[ing], or hunt[ing], or ․ carry[ing] a gun, upon any person's land, whereon there shall be a seated plantation, without the owner's leave,” J.A. 108 (1715 Md. Laws, No. 73); (2) the 1721 Pennsylvania law and 1722 New Jersey law prohibiting carriage or hunting “on the improved or inclosed lands of any plantation other than his own, unless have license or permission,” id. at 113, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (1721 Pa. Laws, ch. 246); see also id. at 119, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (1722 N.J. Laws, ch. 35); (3) the 1763 New York law prohibiting “carry[ing], shoot[ing] or discharg[ing]” any firearm in any “Orchard, Garden, Corn-Field, or other inclosed Land ․ without License” from the proprietor, id. at 124, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (1763 N.Y. Laws, ch. 1233); (4) the 1865 Louisiana law and 1866 Texas law prohibiting carriage on the “premises plantations of any citizen, without the consent of the owner or proprietor,” id. at 137 (1865 La. Acts 14); see also id. at 144, 99 S.Ct. 2213 (1866 Tex. Gen. Laws ch. 90); and (5) the 1893 Oregon law prohibiting anyone “other than an officer on lawful business, [from] being armed ․ or trespass[ing] upon any enclosed premises or lands without the consent of the owner,” id. at 151, 134 S.Ct. 2334 (1893 Or. Laws 79). The State urges that the restricted locations regulation is consistent with these historical statutes. We disagree.
We assume without deciding that the State's analogues demonstrate a well-established and representative tradition of creating a presumption against carriage on enclosed private lands, i.e., private land closed to the public. But we do not agree that these laws support the broader tradition the State urges. These analogues are inconsistent with the restricted location provision's default presumption against carriage on private property open to the public.
The State fails to place § 265.01-d within a national tradition because at least three of its proffered analogues burdened law-abiding citizens’ rights for different reasons than § 265.01-d, and all of its analogues burden Second Amendment rights to a significantly lesser extent than § 265.01-d. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 29, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (identifying “how and why the regulations burden a law-abiding citizen's right to armed self-defense” as central considerations in the history-and-analogue test). We address each issue in turn.
At least three of the State's proffered analogues were explicitly motivated by a substantially different reason (deterring unlicensed hunting) than the restricted location regulation (preventing gun violence). As the State's own brief concedes, the 1721 Pennsylvania statute, 1722 New Jersey statute, and 1763 New York statute were all aimed at preventing the “damages and inconveniencies” caused “by persons carrying guns and presuming to hunt on other people's land.” J.A. at 113 (1721 Pa. Laws, ch. 246) (emphasis added); id. at 119, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (1722 N.J. Laws) (1722 New Jersey statute driven by the “great Damages and Inconveniences arisen by Persons carrying of Guns and presuming to hunt on other Peoples Land); id. at 123–24, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (1763 N.Y. Laws, ch. 1233) (1763 New York statute intended to “more effectually [ ] punish and prevent” the “Practice of Great Numbers of idle and disorderly persons ․ to hunt with Fire-Arms”).122 Similarly, the 1715 Maryland statute prohibited only convicted criminals from carrying a firearm on “any person's land, whereon there shall be a seated plantation, without the owner's leave,” id. at 108, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (1715 Md. Laws, No. 73). No matter how expansively we analogize, we do not see how a tradition of prohibiting illegal hunting on private lands supports prohibiting the lawful carriage of firearms for self-defense on private property open the public.
What is more, none of the State's proffered analogues burdened Second Amendment rights in the same way as § 265.01-d. All of the State's analogues appear to, by their own terms, have created a default presumption against carriage only on private lands not open to the public. The three analogues just cited above, as well as the 1715 Maryland statute, prevented guns on “land,” J.A. at 108 (1715 Md. Laws, No. 73), “improved or inclosed lands,” id. at 133, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (1721 Pa. Laws, ch. 246) and id. at 119, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (1722 N.J. Laws, ch. 35) (prohibiting same), or on any “Orchard, Garden, Cornfield, or other inclosed Land,” id. at 124, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (1763 N.Y. Laws, ch. 1233). Meanwhile, even those statutes that were not limited by their terms to hunting prevented carriage on “any Lands not [one's] own,” id. at 127, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (1771 N.J. Laws, ch. 540 (An Act for the Preservation of Deer and other Game, and to prevent trespassing with Guns)), “the premises or plantations of any citizen,” id. at 137 (1865 La. Acts 14) and id. at 144, 99 S.Ct. 2213 (1866 Tex. Gen. Laws ch. 90) (1866 Texas statute), or the “enclosed premises or lands” of another, id. at 151, 134 S.Ct. 2334 (1893 Or. Laws 79). As it has been developed thus far, the historical record indicates that “land,” “improved or inclosed land” and “premises or plantations” would have been understood to refer to private land not open to the public.123 The State has produced no evidence that those terms were in fact otherwise understood to apply to private property open to the public or that the statutes were in practice applied to private property open to the public. Given that most spaces in a community that are not private homes will be composed of private property open to the public to which § 265.01-d applies, the restricted location provision functionally creates a universal default presumption against carrying firearms in public places, seriously burdening lawful gun owners’ Second Amendment rights. That burden is entirely out of step with that imposed by the proffered analogues, which appear to have created a presumption against carriage only on private property not open to the public.
In sum, the State's analogues fail to establish a national tradition motivated by a similar “how” or “why” of regulating firearms in property open to the public in the manner attempted by § 265.01-d. Accordingly, the State has not carried its burden under Bruen.
Because the State has failed to situate § 265.01-d’s prohibition on carriage on private property open to the public, we affirm the district court's injunction as applied to such property. But the district court nonetheless erred in issuing a blanket injunction that applied to both private property open to the public and private property not open to the public.
The district court accepted the State's argument that § 265.01-d could, consistent with the Second Amendment, be applied to restrict carriage on private property closed to the public. Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 343 (“[T]o the extent to which [§ 265.01-d] restricts concealed carry on privately owned property that is not open to the public ․ the Second Amendment is not the best place to look for protection from that restriction, because thus far the Second Amendment has been found to protect the right to keep and bear arms for self-defense only in one's own home or in public.” (emphasis in original)). Having accepted the State's argument that there was at least one set of circumstances in which the statute could be valid under the Second Amendment, it was error for the district court to subsequently enjoin § 265.01-d in all its applications.124 See Wash. State Grange, 552 U.S. at 449–50, 128 S.Ct. 1184 (“[A] plaintiff can only succeed in a facial challenge by establishing that no set of circumstances exists under which the [statute] would be valid, i.e., that the law is unconstitutional in all of its applications.” (internal quotation marks omitted and alterations adopted)).125
* * *
For the reasons stated above, we MODIFY and AFFIRM the district court's injunction as to § 265.01-d to enjoin enforcement of that provision only with respect to private property open to the public; and REMAND the preliminary injunction as to § 265.01-d with respect to private property not open to the public for further merits analysis consistent with this opinion.
CONCLUSION
For the reasons stated above, we AFFIRM the injunction in part, VACATE in part, and REMAND for proceedings consistent with this opinion. In summary, we uphold the district court's injunctions with respect to N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(1)(o)(iv) (social media disclosure) and N.Y. Penal L. § 265.01-d (restricted locations) as applied to private property held open to the general public. We vacate the injunction in all other respects, having concluded either that the district court lacked jurisdiction because no plaintiff had Article III standing to challenge the laws or that the challenged laws do not violate the Constitution on their face.126
FOOTNOTES
1. Plaintiffs also base a part of one challenge on the First Amendment. The law governing that argument will be described in connection with that claim.
2. The definition of the terms “shall issue” licensing regime and “sensitive place” are explained further below. See infra Background §§ I.A–B, III.D.
3. No party in the three related cases—Hardaway v. Chiumento, 22-2933-cv, Christian v. Chiumento, 22-2987-cv, and Spencer v. Chiumento, 22-3237-cv—petitioned for certiorari. Thus, the Supreme Court did not vacate the judgments in those cases. Accordingly, after some procedural complications following the remand in Antonyuk, the mandates in Hardaway, Christian, and Spencer have been reinstated, and our prior consolidated opinion, Antonyuk v. Chiumento, 89 F.4th 271 (2d Cir. 2023), remains binding on the parties in those three cases. We therefore have no occasion to revisit our prior consolidated opinion as it relates to the issues in those cases, and our discussion of those issues remains good law in the Circuit.
4. Nor was proper cause a requirement for certain classes of people to possess a concealed firearm under certain conditions. See, e.g., N.Y. Penal L. § 400.00(2)(b)-(e) (effective Apr. 3, 2021, to July 5, 2022) (“a merchant or storekeeper” “in his place of business”; “a messenger employed by a banking institution or express company” “while so employed”; “a justice of the supreme court in the first or second judicial departments,” or “a judge of the New York city civil court or the New York city criminal court”; certain employees of correctional or detention institutions, as approved by an appropriate supervisor).
5. The CCIA was amended on May 3, 2023, during the pendency of this appeal, to narrow its provisions applicable to places of worship and public parks. See Ch. 55, pt. F, § 1, 2023 N.Y. Laws. In particular, persons “responsible for security” at places of worship are now exempt from the place-of-worship prohibition, and the term “public parks” has been defined to exclude specially defined forest preserves and privately owned land within public parks. Id. Those amendments took immediate effect. Id. § 4. We discuss the impact of those amendments on this appeal below.
6. By operation of Federal Rule of Appellate Procedure 43(c)(2), Defendant-Appellant Steven G. James was automatically substituted as a Defendant-Appellant after assuming the office of Superintendent of the New York State Police. He replaced previous Defendant-Appellant Steven A. Nigrelli. Because former-Superintendent Nigrelli was a Defendant-Appellant when briefs were filed, the opinion cites to briefs filed on Nigrelli's behalf.
7. Plaintiffs do not challenge the district court's ruling that they lacked standing to challenge the sensitive-locations provision as applied to: (1) any place under the control of federal, state, or local government for purposes of government administration; (2) libraries; (3) the location of any program that provides services to children and youth, or any legally exempt childcare provider; (4) summer camps; (5) the location of any program regulated, operated, or funded by the Office for People with Developmental Disabilities; (6) the location of any program regulated, operated, or funded by the Office of Addiction Services and Supports; (7) the location of any program regulated, operated, or funded by the Office of Mental Health; (8) the location of any program regulated, operated, or funded by the Office of Temporary and Disability Assistance; (9) homeless shelters, family shelters, domestic violence shelters, and emergency shelters; (10) residential settings licensed, certified, regulated, funded, or operated by the Department of Health; (11) any building or grounds of any educational institutions, colleges, school districts, and private schools; and (12) the area commonly known as Times Square. Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 261, 267, 273–74, 275, 276–79, 292. Also unchallenged is the district court's ruling that Governor Hochul was not a proper defendant because she does not have or exercise sufficient enforcement authority over the CCIA. Id. at 295–96.
8. In Hardaway v. Chiumento, we vacated the district court's preliminary injunction against enforcement of the place of worship provision, § 265.01-e(2)(c). Antonyuk, 89 F.4th at 345. In Spencer v. Chiumento, we affirmed the district court's preliminary injunction, which prohibited enforcement of the place of worship provision, § 265.01-e(2)(c), against the plaintiffs in that case. Id. at 346. In Christian v. Nigrelli, we affirmed the district court's injunction, which prohibited enforcement of the restricted location provision as it applies to private property open to the public, § 265.01-d, against the plaintiffs in that case. Id. at 386. As noted above, see note 3, no party sought our review of those rulings, and we have no occasion to revisit them here.
9. Before Heller, Second Amendment issues were rarely litigated in federal court. Not until adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment was it understood that any provision of the Bill of Rights applied to the States, see Barron v. City of Baltimore, 32 U.S. 7 Pet. 243, 250–51, 8 L.Ed. 672 (1833), and even after adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, the Supreme Court reaffirmed that the Second Amendment “means no more than that it shall not be infringed by Congress,” United States v. Cruikshank, 92 U.S. 542, 553, 23 L.Ed. 588 (1875). Shortly after Congress began passing firearms regulations in the first half of the 20th century, most notably in the National Firearms Act of 1934 and then the Federal Firearms Act of 1938, the Supreme Court instructed courts and litigants that the Second Amendment “must be interpreted and applied” in light of its “obvious purpose to assure the continuation and render possible the effectiveness” of the well-regulated militia. United States v. Miller, 307 U.S. 174, 178, 59 S.Ct. 816, 83 L.Ed. 1206 (1939). To that end, the Supreme Court in Miller rejected a Second Amendment challenge to a federal prohibition on possessing sawed-off shotguns because there was no evidence that such weapons had “some reasonable relationship to the preservation or efficiency of a well regulated militia.” Id. Dissenting in Heller, Justice Stevens pointed out that “hundreds of judges ha[d] relied on [Miller’s] view of the Amendment,” and that the Court had in fact reaffirmed that view in 1980. Heller, 554 U.S. at 638 & n.2, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (citing Lewis v. United States, 445 U.S. 55, 65–66 n.8, 100 S.Ct. 915, 63 L.Ed.2d 198 (1980)).
10. Gould v. Morgan, 907 F.3d 659, 668–69 (1st Cir. 2018); United States v. Marzzarella, 614 F.3d 85, 89 (3d Cir. 2010); United States v. Chester, 628 F.3d 673, 680–83 (4th Cir. 2010); National Rifle Ass'n of Am., Inc. v. Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms, and Explosives, 700 F.3d 185, 194–95 (5th Cir. 2012); United States v. Greeno, 679 F.3d 510, 518 (6th Cir. 2012); Ezell v. City of Chicago, 651 F.3d 684, 700–04 (7th Cir. 2011); Young v. Hawaii, 992 F.3d 765, 783 (9th Cir. 2021) (en banc), United States v. Reese, 627 F.3d 792, 800–01 (10th Cir. 2010), GeorgiaCarry.Org, Inc. v. Georgia, 687 F.3d 1244, 1260 n.34 (11th Cir. 2012); Heller v. District of Columbia (Heller II), 670 F.3d 1244, 1252 (D.C. Cir. 2011).
11. Accord Ocean State Tactical, LLC v. Rhode Island, 95 F.4th 38, 43 (1st Cir. 2024); United States v. Dorsey, 105 F.4th 526, 530–31 (3d Cir. 2024); Maryland Shall Issue, Inc. v. Moore, 116 F.4th 211, 218–19 (4th Cir. 2024) (en banc); United States v. Diaz, 116 F.4th 458, 463–64 (5th Cir. 2024); United States v. Williams, 113 F.4th 637, 648 (6th Cir. 2024); United States v. Miles, 86 F.4th 734, 740 (7th Cir. 2023); Worth v. Jacobson, 108, F.4th 677, 687–88 (8th Cir. 2024); Wolford v. Lopez, 116 F.4th 959, 976–77 (9th Cir. 2024); see also Vincent v. Garland, 80 F.4th 1197, 1200 (10th Cir. 2023), cert. granted, judgment vacated, ––– U.S. ––––, 144 S. Ct. 2708, ––– L.Ed.2d –––– (2024); Nat'l Rifle Ass'n v. Bondi, 61 F.4th 1317, 1321 (11th Cir. 2023), vacated pending reh'g en banc, 72 F.4th 1346 (11th Cir. 2023).
12. Justice Kavanaugh, joined by Chief Justice Roberts, emphasized that “[t]he Court's decision addresses only the unusual discretionary licensing regimes, known as ‘may-issue’ regimes, that are employed by 6 States including New York,” under which a licensing official has “open-ended discretion” to deny concealed-carry licenses and may deny a license for a failure to “show some special need apart from self-defense.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 79, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (Kavanaugh, J., concurring). “Those features,” Justice Kavanaugh wrote, “in effect deny the right to carry handguns for self-defense to many ordinary, law-abiding citizens.” Id. (internal quotation marks omitted). Accordingly, the Court did not address “objective shall-issue licensing regimes,” under which the State “may require a license applicant to undergo fingerprinting, a background check, a mental health records check, and training in firearms handling and in laws regarding the use of force, among other possible requirements.” Id. at 80, 142 S.Ct. 2111. “Unlike New York's may-issue regime, those shall-issue regimes do not grant open-ended discretion to licensing officials and do not require a showing of some special need apart from self-defense.” Id. Shall-issue regimes are constitutional, Justice Kavanaugh explained, so long as they “operate in [an objective] manner in practice.” Id.
13. The Court left open the question as to how to identify the level of generality at which to compare the problems addressed by contemporary legislatures with those being addressed in 1791 or 1868 to determine whether those problems are the same.
14. See Jacob D. Charles, The Dead Hand of a Silent Past: Bruen, Gun Rights, and the Shackles of History, 73 Duke L.J. 67, 153 (2023) (criticizing such an inference because it “elevates mere unregulated conduct to the status of inviolate constitutional right”).
15. While the law review article also cited several more 19th-century and Reconstruction Era laws supporting prohibitions at polling places and courthouses, see Kopel & Greenlee, supra, at 245–47, Bruen’s analysis was independent of those laws, cf. 597 U.S. at 37, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (declining to address “whether courts should primarily rely on the prevailing understanding of” the right to keep and bear arms from around 1791 (the Second Amendment's ratification) or 1868 (the Fourteenth Amendment's ratification)). And, to the extent Bruen did rely on those later prohibitions, that confirms our conclusion that courts—rather than ignoring laws because they are “too old” or not “old enough”—should consider this Nation's whole tradition.
16. In their petition for certiorari in this case, Plaintiffs asked the Supreme Court to resolve the debate about whether courts may rely on the prevailing understanding of the Second Amendment when the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified in 1868. See Petition for Cert. at 10–17. As the Rahimi Court left that issue open, we perceive no reason to revisit our conclusion that we should consider the prevailing understanding of the right to bear arms in both 1868 and 1791.
17. Although this may suggest that the values articulated in Bruen would tolerate reference to a more expansive sweep of time, we are careful to limit our analysis to the two relevant historical moments and the periods close around them. See 597 U.S. at 35, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“[W]e must also guard against giving postenactment history more weight than it can rightly bear.”). That is a useful discipline, and may be necessary, for thinking about the Second Amendment in a way that avoids inconsistency, cherry-picking, and special pleading.
18. See Josh Blackman & Ilya Shapiro, Keeping Pandora's Box Sealed: Privileges or Immunities, the Constitution in 2020, and Properly Extending the Right to Keep and Bear Arms to the States, 8 Geo. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 1, 52 (2010) (“Analyzing the meaning of the right to keep and bear arms in 1791 was proper in Heller, because the Second Amendment in that case only applied to the federal government. In McDonald, however, the key year is 1868, and the Court should look at evidence from the time of Reconstruction, not the time of the Revolution.”); Steven G. Calabresi & Sarah E. Agudo, Individual Rights Under State Constitutions When the Fourteenth Amendment Was Ratified in 1868: What Rights Are Deeply Rooted in American History and Tradition?, 87 Tex. L. Rev. 7, 115–16 (2008) (“We think [Akhil] Amar is exactly right that for those wondering about incorporation or judicial protection against the states of unenumerated rights in federal constitutional law, the question is controlled not by the original meaning of the first ten Amendments in 1791 but instead by the meaning those texts and the Fourteenth Amendment had in 1868.”).
19. Plaintiffs challenged other aspects of the licensing regime in the district court, including provisions that require concealed carry applicants to attend an in-person interview with the licensing officer, submit a list of four character references, and complete 18 hours of in-person firearms training. The district court concluded that Plaintiffs had not demonstrated substantial likelihood of success on these claims and accordingly denied preliminary relief with respect to those provisions. See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 307, 314, 316. Plaintiffs have not cross-appealed from or otherwise challenged those rulings here, so we express no view on them.
20. The appellants filed two briefs: one on behalf of former defendant Nigrelli and defendant Doran, and one on behalf of defendant Cecile. We cite the former as “Nigrelli Br.” and the latter as “Cecile Br.”
21. Decastro can be read as a case about injury—and failure to apply for a license is sometimes best understood that way—but Decastro's criminal conviction surely qualified as an Article III injury-in-fact. Instead, we understand his standing to have faltered on traceability: his refusal to use the state's licensing procedure severed the causal chain connecting the challenged rule to his conviction. Similarly, Jackson-Bey v. Hanslmaier, 115 F.3d 1091 (2d Cir. 1997)—a case on which Decastro and many other decisions in this area rely—also sounds in traceability. There, a prison had forbidden an inmate from wearing certain religious garb to his father's funeral. We acknowledged that while the plaintiff had been injured, he lacked standing because he had neither registered his religious affiliation (enabling him to wear the garb) or shown that such registration would have been futile. Accordingly, any injury was traceable not to the defendants but to “his own decision not to follow the simple procedure of registering his religion.” 115 F.3d at 1095.
22. The full quote from Parker—which the Supreme Court affirmed as District of Columbia v. Heller—makes clear that the D.C. Circuit was opining on Heller's injury, not making a blanket statement about all licensing challenges: “[Heller] is not asserting that his injury is only a threatened prosecution, nor is he claiming only a general right to handgun ownership; he is asserting a right to a registration certificate, the denial of which is his distinct injury.” 478 F.3d at 376 (emphasis added). And the D.C. Circuit was correct: Heller's constitutional claim centered on his ineligibility for a license and was thus akin to those in Decastro, Libertarian Party, and Bruen. See id. (“[Heller] invoked his rights under the Second Amendment to challenge the statutory classifications used to bar his ownership of a handgun under D.C. law.”).
23. Desiderio and Sammon are framed in terms of ripeness rather than standing, but we understand them to apply the same justiciability principles as failure-to-apply cases using a standing framing. See Nat'l Org. for Marriage, Inc. v. Walsh, 714 F.3d 682, 688 (2d Cir. 2013) (“Often, the best way to think of constitutional ripeness is as a specific application of the actual injury aspect of Article III standing.”); 13B Wright & Miller, Fed. Prac. & Proc. Juris. § 3531.12 (3d ed.) (“Although discrete names have been given to the several nominate categories of justiciability, they are tied closely together. ․ The most direct connections run between standing and ripeness.”). We have expressly noted that arguments of this type sound in both standing and ripeness. Bach, 408 F.3d at 82 & n.15 (defendants’ “ ‘standing’ objection” regarding plaintiff's failure to apply for license “might also be understood as a ripeness challenge”); see also Image Carrier, 567 F.2d at 1201–02 (construing argument that plaintiff “should have bid for City work and been turned down in order to present a justiciable claim” as sounding in ripeness instead of standing).
24. See 1913 N.Y. Laws ch. 608, § 1, p. 1629 (“It shall be lawful for any magistrate, upon proof before him that the person applying therefor is of good moral character ․ to issue to such person a license to have and carry concealed a pistol or revolver ․”).
25. See Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (“[W]hatever else it leaves to future evaluation, [the Second Amendment] surely elevates above all other interests the right of law-abiding, responsible citizens to use arms in defense of hearth and home.”); Bruen, 597 U.S. at 8–9, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (summarizing Heller and McDonald as “recogniz[ing] that the Second and Fourteenth Amendments protect the right of an ordinary, law-abiding citizen to possess a handgun in the home for self-defense,” and framing its own holding as extending only that right to public carry (emphasis added)); id. at 38, 142 S.Ct. 2111 n.9 (suggesting that licensing regimes which “do not necessarily prevent ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens’ from exercising their Second Amendment right to public carry” and instead “are designed to ensure only that those bearing arms in the jurisdiction are, in fact, ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens’ ” are consistent with Bruen’s analysis); id. at 70, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“Nor ․ have American governments required law-abiding, responsible citizens to [show proper cause] ․ in order to carry arms in public.”); see also United States v. Jimenez, 895 F.3d 228, 234–35 (2d Cir. 2018) (“The Supreme Court thus identified the core of Second Amendment protections by reference not only to particular uses and particular weapons but also to particular persons, namely, those who are ‘law-abiding and responsible.’ ”); United States v. Bryant, 711 F.3d 364, 369 (2d Cir. 2013) (“We read [Heller's] exegesis as an implicit limitation on the exercise of the Second Amendment right to bear arms for ‘lawful purposes,’ and a limitation on ownership to that of ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens.’ ” (alteration adopted) (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 628, 630, 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783)).
26. In Rahimi, the Supreme Court also rejected, in dictum, the government's argument that the Second Amendment does not protect the “irresponsible,” although it did not address other terms used to define the Amendment's scope, such as “law-abiding.” 144 S. Ct. at 1903. That dictum is addressed further below. See infra note 30.
27. This assumption obviates a related question that divided the Fourth Circuit in Maryland Shall Issue, Inc. v. Moore: whether shall-issue licensing requirements are sufficiently burdensome to “infringe” the right to keep and bear arms. Compare 116 F.4th at 221–23, with id. at 230 (Rushing, J., concurring in the judgment).
28. See Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (“[W]hatever else [the Second Amendment] leaves to future evaluation, it surely elevates above all other interests the right of law-abiding, responsible citizens to use arms in defense of hearth and home.”); Bruen, 597 U.S. at 8–9, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“[T]he Second and Fourteenth Amendments protect the right of an ordinary, law-abiding citizen to possess a handgun in the home for self-defense ․ [and] publicly for their self-defense.”).
29. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 38 n.9, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“[N]othing in our analysis should be interpreted to suggest the unconstitutionality of the 43 States’ ‘shall-issue’ licensing regimes” as “they do not necessarily prevent ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens’ from exercising their Second Amendment right to public carry” and “are designed to ensure only that those bearing arms in the jurisdiction are, in fact, ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens.’ ” (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783)).
30. The Supreme Court in Rahimi weighed in on this issue, rejecting the government's argument that Rahimi could be convicted consistently with the Second Amendment simply because the protection order demonstrated that he was not “responsible.” 144 S. Ct. at 1903 (quotation marks omitted). The Court noted that the references to “responsibility” in its earlier decisions were dicta. Id. Of course, the statement in Rahimi was itself dictum; the Court had already upheld the statute because Rahimi was dangerous. Id. at 1902. Just as in Heller and Bruen, the question of whether a person who was not dangerous but who could fairly be characterized as “not responsible” could be disarmed consistent with the Second Amendment “was simply not presented.” Id. at 1903.The fact that this statement in Rahimi was dictum does not mean that we may disregard it, any more than we may disregard the portion of the Bruen majority's historical analysis that went beyond what was necessary to decide the case, or the Court's references to gun possession in schools and courthouses in Bruen and Heller, which addressed matters beyond the issues raised in those cases. As the Court persuasively observed, “[ir]responsible is a vague term.” Id. (quotation marks omitted). Still, the Court did not face, and therefore did not definitively rule on, the constitutionality of a licensing regime that adopted some specific and narrow definition of “responsibility.”We need not address such a case either. New York's “good moral character” requirement is plainly capable of constitutional application to dangerous persons—who are the core target of that requirement. New York's licensing authorities would be well advised to pay careful attention to the Court's concern about loose application of that requirement to those individuals who could be characterized as “irresponsible.”
31. Compare Kanter, 919 F.3d at 451, 454–64 (Barrett, J., dissenting) (“History is consistent with common sense: it demonstrates that legislatures have the power to prohibit dangerous people from possessing guns. But that power extends only to people who are dangerous.”); Binderup, 836 F.3d at 369 (Hardiman, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgments) (“[T]he public understanding of the scope of the Second Amendment was tethered to the principle that the Constitution permitted the dispossession of persons who demonstrated that they would present a danger to the public if armed.”); Folajtar v. Att'y Gen. of the U.S., 980 F.3d 897, 914 (3d Cir. 2020) (Bibas, J., dissenting) (similar); Range, 69 F.4th at 110 (Ambro, J., concurring) (federal prohibition on felons possessing guns is constitutional in almost all applications “because it fits within our Nation's history and tradition of disarming those persons who legislatures believed would, if armed, pose a threat to the orderly functioning of society”); Joseph G.S. Greenlee, The Historical Justification for Prohibiting Dangerous Persons from Possessing Arms, 20 Wyo. L. Rev. 249 (2020), with United States v. Jackson, 69 F.4th 495, 502–05 (8th Cir. 2023) (describing this debate and holding that either view supports the federal prohibition on all felons possessing guns: “[L]egislatures traditionally employed status-based restrictions to disqualify categories of persons from possessing firearms. Whether those actions are best characterized as restrictions on persons who deviated from legal norms or persons who presented an unacceptable risk of dangerousness, Congress acted within the historical tradition when it enacted § 922(g)(1) and the prohibition on possession of firearms by felons.”); Range v. Att'y Gen. of U.S., 53 F.4th 262, 273–74 (3d Cir. 2022), rev'd en banc 69 F.4th 96 (3d Cir. 2023) (concluding that the Second Amendment permits disarmament not just of dangerous individuals but also “those who have demonstrated disregard for the rule of law through the commission of felony and felony-equivalent offenses, whether or not those crimes are violent.”); Binderup, 836 F.3d at 348 (lead opinion) (“People who have committed or are likely to commit ‘violent offenses’ ․ undoubtedly qualify as ‘unvirtuous citizens’ who lack Second Amendment rights. ․ The category of ‘unvirtuous citizens’ is ․ broader than violent criminals; it covers any person who has committed a serious criminal offense, violent or nonviolent.”); United States v. Carpio-Leon, 701 F.3d 974, 979–80 (4th Cir. 2012) (characterizing tradition in terms of “virtuousness”); United States v. Yancey, 621 F.3d 681, 684–85 (7th Cir. 2010) (same); United States v. Vongxay, 594 F.3d 1111, 1118 (9th Cir. 2010) (same); Saul Cornell & Nathan DeDino, A Well Regulated Right: The Early American Origins of Gun Control, 73 Fordham L. Rev. 487, 491–92 (2004); Glenn Harlan Reynolds, A Critical Guide to the Second Amendment, 62 Tenn. L. Rev. 461, 480 (1995); Don B. Kates, Jr., The Second Amendment: A Dialogue, Law & Contemp. Probs., Winter 1986, at 143, 146.
32. We thus agree with the Fourth Circuit that “despite some delay occasioned by ‘shall-issue’ permit processes, this type of licensing law is presumptively constitutional because it operates merely to ensure that individuals seeking to exercise their Second Amendment rights are ‘law-abiding’ persons.” Maryland Shall Issue, Inc. v. Moore, No. 21-2017, 2024 WL 3908548, at *1 (4th Cir. Aug. 23, 2024) (en banc).
33. In their petition for certiorari, Plaintiffs argued that Bruen does not allow governments to disarm individuals based on mere “[p]remonitions of [d]angerousness,” and that the character requirement inappropriately vests officials with discretion to determine whether an individual is likely to pose a danger to society in the future. Pet. for Cert. at 34. But, in upholding the constitutionality of 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(8), the Rahimi Court relied on historical precedents involving such forward-looking determinations—the surety laws. See Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1899–900. As Rahimi explained, the surety laws, “[a] form of ‘preventive justice,’ ” empowered magistrates to require those individuals “[of] whom there is a probable ground to suspect of future misbehaviour” to post a bond as a condition for firearm possession. Id. (quoting 4 Blackstone 251) (alteration in original). Thus, Rahimi reinforces our original conclusions in this case.
34. Indeed, such an appeal is likely a prerequisite to an Article 78 proceeding, which does not permit review of “determination[s] [ ] which ․ can be adequately reviewed by appeal ․ to some other body.” N.Y. C.P.L.R. § 7801(1); see, e.g., Essex County v. Zagata, 91 N.Y. 2d 447, 453, 672 N.Y.S.2d 281, 695 N.E.2d 232 (1998). Similarly, it is doubtful that a plaintiff who brings a federal suit challenging an initial denial before seeking administrative review would present a ripe case or controversy.
35. We also leave open challenges based on a de facto pattern of denials or de jure interpretation of the provision which impermissibly restricts the right to carry a gun in public. Cf. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 38 n.9, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“[B]ecause any permitting scheme can be put toward abusive ends, we do not rule out constitutional challenges to shall-issue regimes where, for example, lengthy wait times in processing license applications or exorbitant fees deny ordinary citizens their right to public carry.”).
36. As we explained supra, evidence from the Reconstruction Era regarding the scope of the right to bear arms incorporated by the Fourteenth Amendment is at least as relevant as evidence from the Founding Era regarding the Second Amendment itself. The period of relevance extends past 1868. Laws enacted in 1878 or even 1888 were likely drafted or voted on by members of the same generation that ratified the Fourteenth Amendment and thus remain probative as to the meaning of that Amendment.
37. The State—and this Court—relies on and incorporates by reference the catalog of 43 licensing ordinances compiled in an amicus brief filed with the Supreme Court in Bruen by historian Patrick J. Charles. See Brief of Amicus Curiae Patrick J. Charles in Support of Neither Party, App'x 1, N.Y. State Rifle and Pistol Ass'n v. Bruen, 597 U.S. 1, 142 S.Ct. 2111, 213 L.Ed.2d 387 (2022) (No. 20-843) (hereinafter, “Charles Amicus Br.”). We cite only a sample of Mr. Charles's list, which he in turn represents to be “only a sample of the nearly 300 laws governing the carrying of concealed and dangerous weapons that [he] has researched.” Id. at App'x 1. We also note a (partially co-extensive) list of discretionary city licensing regimes in Patrick J. Charles, The Faces of the Second Amendment Outside the Home, Take Two: How We Got Here and Why It Matters, 64 Clev. St. L. Rev. 373, 419 n.245 (2016).
38. The Municipal Code of St. Louis § 8 (1881).
39. Spokane, Wash., Ordinance No. A544, § 1 (Jan. 2, 1895), reprinted in The Municipal Code of the City of Spokane, Washington 309–10 (Rose M. Denny ed., 1896).
40. Licensing schemes were a post-Civil War phenomenon. E.g., Brief of Amici Curiae Profs. of Hist. & L. in Supp. of Resps. at 22, N.Y. State Rifle and Pistol Ass'n v. Bruen, 597 U.S. 1, 142 S.Ct. 2111, 213 L.Ed.2d 387 (2022) (No. 20-843) (hereinafter, “Profs.’ Amicus Br.”) (“In the latter half of the nineteenth century, many municipalities also began to enact licensing schemes, pursuant to which individuals had to obtain permission to carry dangerous weapons in public.”); Charles Amicus Br. at 7–9; Saul Cornell, History and Tradition or Fantasy and Fiction: Which Version of the Past Will the Supreme Court Choose in NYSRPA v. Bruen?, 49 Hastings Const. L.Q. 145, 168–71 (2022). See also infra.
41. Twentieth-century evidence is not as probative as nineteenth-century evidence because it is less proximate to the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment. Bruen cautions “against giving postenactment history more weight than it can rightly bear.” 597 U.S. at 35, 142 S.Ct. 2111. But such laws are not weightless. The Bruen Court's concern was with temporally distant laws inconsistent with prior practices. See id. at 36, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“[P]ostratification adoption or acceptance of laws that are inconsistent with the original meaning of the constitutional text obviously cannot overcome or alter that text.” (quotation omitted); see also id. (“[T]o the extent later history contradicts what the text says, the text controls.” (emphasis added)). In contrast, when laws which otherwise might be too recent when considered in isolation nonetheless reflect previously settled practices and assumptions, they remain probative as to the existence of an American tradition of regulation.
42. “Laws granting the authorities discretion over the issue of concealed carry permits, ‘may issue’ laws, predominated in the early post-World War II period: by 1960, only two states, Vermont and New Hampshire, had ‘shall issue’ laws.” Richard S. Grossman & Stephen A. Lee, May Issue Versus Shall Issue: Explaining the Pattern of Concealed Carry Handgun Laws, 1960–2001, 26 Contemp. Econ. Pol. 198, 200 (2008); see also Robert J. Spitzer, Gun Law History in the United States and Second Amendment Rights, 80 L. & Contemp. Probs. 55, 62 (2017) (“[A]s late as 1981, only two states of the union had loose, ‘shall issue’ carry laws ․ Nineteen states barred concealed gun carrying entirely, and twenty-eight states had ‘may issue’ laws, where states have great discretion as to whether to issue carry permits.” (footnotes omitted)); Cramer & Kopel, supra, at 680 (noting that in 1995 “[a]bout one-third of all states have adopted laws or practices ․ requir[ing] that after passing a background check (and sometimes a firearms safety class), eligible persons must be granted [a concealed-carry] permit if they apply”).The district court appears to have based its conclusion that purely objective licensing schemes are required by history on Bruen’s statement that non-discretionary licensing regimes are dominant now. See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 35 at 302. But Bruen made no historical claim about discretionary licensing; the fact that a given form of regulation is popular now is irrelevant to whether a different regulation is part of the Nation's tradition of firearm regulation. In any event, as we explain below, we count at least twenty-three licensing regimes that still call for discretionary judgments by licensing officers.
43. The district court reasonably sought methodological guidance in Bruen, a challenge undertaken only a few short months after that decision was handed down. We have no doubt that the court's analysis was driven by a desire to apply Bruen faithfully—we now play our part by offering further guidance for how to assess the historical record future in cases.
44. In 1790, the Nation's largest urban area (New York City) had a population of 33,000. In 1880, the census counted 1,206,299 people, not to mention a further half-million across the East River in still-independent Brooklyn. See Campbell Gibson, Population of the 100 Largest Cities and Other Urban Places In The United States: 1790 to 1990, tbls. 2 & 11 (U.S. Census Working Paper No. POP-WP027), available at https://www.census.gov/library/working-papers/1998/demo/POP-twps0027.html#urban [https://perma.cc/KK43-HBEA]. The Nation was 5.1% urban in 1790; 28.2% in 1880. Urban expansion was especially concentrated in the Northeast, where 50.8% of people were city-dwellers in 1880. U.S. Census Bureau, United States Summary: 2010 — Population and Housing Unit Counts, at 20 tbl. 10 (Sept. 2012), available at https://www2.census.gov/library/publications/decennial/2010/cph-2/cph-2-1.pdf [https://perma.cc/ZJF5-976W]. As historian Eric Monkkonen summarized it:In both structure and form, the modern American city was born in the nineteenth century, a century of dramatic transformation on practically every front. ․ [T]he century-long period of local economic and population growth from 1830 to 1930 saw a dynamic and historically unprecedented expansion of cities—in absolute size, in proportion, and in number.Eric H. Monkkonen, America Becomes Urban 4–5 (1988).
45. Similarly, historian Jack Rakove has questioned whether the Founders would have even recognized the problem confronting policymakers of today (or of the post-Civil War period):[B]ecause eighteenth-century firearms were not nearly as threatening or lethal as those available today, we ․ cannot expect the discussants of the late 1780s to have cast their comments about keeping and bearing arms in the same terms that we would. ․ Guns were so difficult to fire in the eighteenth century that the very idea of being accidentally killed by one was itself hard to conceive. Indeed, anyone wanting either to murder his family or protect his home in the eighteenth century would have been better advised (and much more likely) to grab an axe or knife than to load, prime, and discharge a firearm.Jack N. Rakove, The Second Amendment: The Highest State of Originalism, 76 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 103, 110 (2000).
46. Allen Steinberg, The Transformation of Criminal Justice: Philadelphia 1800-1880, at 2 (1989); see also Charles Amicus Br at 7 (“It was not until the nineteenth century that the adaptable and discretionary common law model of criminal law enforcement began to develop into more tangible, concrete forms.” (citing Patrick J. Charles, Armed In America: A History Of Gun Rights From Colonial Militias to Concealed Carry 141–47 (2019)).
47. See Samuel Walker & Charles M. Katz, The Police In America: An Introduction 33–34 (9th ed., 2018); Eric H. Monkkonen, History of Urban Police, 15 Crime & Just. 547, 553 (1992) (“Uniformed police spread across the United States to most cities in the three decades between 1850 and 1880․ [I]n general, a city's rank size among American cities determined the order in which police were adopted, the spread of police innovation following a diffusion curve typical for all sorts of innovations.”).
48. See Charles Amicus Br. at 8–9 (“In the mid-nineteenth century, to meet changing public safety concerns as well as changing social and cultural norms, laws governing the carrying of concealed and dangerous weapons once again began to evolve.”).
49. For those other models of concealed carry restrictions, see, e.g., Saul Cornell, The Right to Carry Firearms Outside of the Home: Separating Historical Myths from Historical Realities, 39 Fordham Urb. L.J. 1695, 1719–25 (2012); Profs.’ Amicus Br. at 14–18; Charles Amicus Br. at 9, App'x 3 & 4.
50. See Steinberg, supra, at 3, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (contrasting the late-nineteenth-century's “administrative and policy-making state” with the “reactive, particularistic, and extremely informal” “early-nineteenth-century local state”); Patrick J. Charles, The Second Amendment and the Basic Right to Transport Firearms for Lawful Purposes, 13 Charleston L. Rev. 1285, 146 (“[B]eginning in the 1860s, corresponding with the growth of statutory law, [a surety system] was gradually phased out in favor of two legal alternatives. ․ The first legal alternative was armed carriage licensing laws.”).
51. Cornell, supra at 171 (citing Eric H. Monkkonen, America Becomes Urban 98–108 (1988)).
52. Tellingly, other commentators on licensing regimes have categorized these states’ regimes as “may-issue.” E.g., Noah C. Chauvin, The Constitutional Incongruity of “May-Issue” Concealed Carry Permit Laws, 31 Univ. Fla. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 227, 230 n.23, 237 (2021).
53. See also Ga. Code Ann. § 16-11-129(b.1)(3) (West 2022) (permitting court to grant exception to general rule against issuing a license to individual with history of mental illness if court finds “that the person will not likely act in a manner dangerous to public safety in carrying a weapon and that granting the relief will not be contrary to the public interest”); Me. Rev. Stat. Ann., Tit. 25, § 2003(1) (2022) (“good moral character”); Minn. Stat. § 624.714 subd. 6(a)(3) (West 2023) (“substantial likelihood that the applicant is a danger to self or the public if authorized to carry a pistol under a permit”); Mont. Code Ann. § 45-8-321(2) (West 2023) (“reasonable cause to believe that the applicant is mentally ill, mentally disordered, or mentally disabled or otherwise may be a threat to the peace and good order of the community to the extent that the applicant should not be allowed to carry a concealed weapon”); Mo. Rev. Stat. § 571.101 (2016) (applicant eligible if he “[h]as not engaged in a pattern of behavior ․ that causes the sheriff to have a reasonable belief that the applicant presents a danger to himself or others”); 18 Pa. Stat. and Cons. Stat. Ann. § 6109(e)(1)(i) (West 2016) (“character and reputation is such that the individual would be likely to act in a manner dangerous to public safety”); id. § 6109(d)(3) (authorizing the sheriff to “investigate whether the applicant's character and reputation are such that the applicant will not be likely to act in a manner dangerous to public safety”); Tex. Gov't Code Ann. § 411.172(a)(7) (West 2021) (“not incapable of exercising sound judgment with respect to the proper use and storage of a handgun”); Utah Code Ann. § 53-5-704(3)(a) (West 2022) (“reasonable cause to believe that the applicant or permit holder has been or is a danger to self or others as demonstrated by evidence” like past violent behavior); Wyo. Stat. Ann. § 6-8-104(g) (West 2021) (“reasonably likely to be a danger to himself or others, or to the community at large as a result of the applicant's mental or psychological state, as demonstrated by a past pattern or practice of behavior”); Va. Code. Ann. § 18.2-308.09(13) (West 2021) (“likely to use a weapon unlawfully or negligently to endanger others”).
54. See also Fla. Stat. Ann. § 790.06 (2023); Idaho Code Ann. § 18-3302(11)(f) (West 2020); La. Stat. Ann. § 40:1379.3(C)(8) (2023); Miss. Code. Ann. § 45-9-101(2)(e), (f) (West 2023); N.M. Stat. Ann. § 29-19-4(A)(9) (West 2023); 18 Pa. Stat. and Cons. Stat. Ann. § 6109(e)(1)(v)–(vii); Tex. Gov't Code Ann. § 411.172(a)(8); Wyo. Stat. Ann. § 6-8-104(b)(vi). Many of these statutes include rebuttable presumptions or other guidance for the licensing officers’ determination, e.g., La. Stat. Ann. § 40:1379.3(C)(8) (establishing presumption that applicant “chronically and habitually uses alcoholic beverages to the extent that his normal faculties are impaired” if he has been convicted of a DUI or admitted to treatment for alcoholism in the past five years), but all ultimately require some exercise of discretion.
55. Justice Kavanaugh's concurrence can be read to posit a categorically anti-discretion view. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 80, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (Kavanaugh, J., concurring) (New York “may continue to require licenses for carrying handguns for self-defense so long as [it] employ[s] objective licensing requirements like those used by the 43 shall-issue states”) (emphasis added). But for the reasons stated above, such a view, if the term “objective” is read strictly literally, is incompatible with footnotes 1 and 9 in the majority opinion (which Justice Kavanaugh joined in full). Further, Justice Kavanaugh's concurring opinion expressly approved of the licensing requirements “used by the 43 shall-issue States,” many of which, as discussed above, call for the exercise of discretion by licensing officials. Id.As the district court pointed out, many 18th-century restrictions aimed at keeping firearms away from people perceived as dangerous were based on readily ascertainable—but overbroad and discriminatory—racial, religious, or political categories. S.A. 99. Judgments based on “objective” characteristics are not inherently more fair than individualized determinations.
56. Although the Court had earlier defined “shall-issue” regimes as those in which officials lack “discretion to deny licenses based on a perceived lack of need or suitability,” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 13, 142 S.Ct. 2111, the Court immediately followed that sentence with footnote 1's explanation that Connecticut and Rhode Island are shall-issue jurisdictions, despite their suitability requirements, because “perceived lack of need” is not a valid basis to deny a license in those states.
57. Rahimi thus serves as a reminder that the principal distinction between the shall-issue licensing regimes that Bruen distinguished from the New York Sullivan Law that Bruen struck down is that the former require officials to grant licenses to any citizen who meets certain requirements, while the latter, unusual today and without prior historical analogy, authorized officials to deny licenses even to law-abiding citizens who did not satisfy the officials that they had a particularized reason, beyond a general desire to protect themselves, for possessing a firearm.
58. The district court distinguished the cohabitant requirement from a character-reference requirement on the ground that the latter dealt with the applicant's public reputation while the former requires disclosure of individuals who may only know about private reputation. See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 307. We are not sure such a distinction is a coherent one. Nor is it meaningful in the context of assessing the burden on the applicant's rights. The information demanded—the names and contact information of persons close to the applicant who can speak to his or her fitness to be licensed to wield a lethal weapon—is the same.
59. As discussed above, we have diligently reconsidered the conclusions reached in our prior opinion in this case—including those in this portion of the opinion—in light of Rahimi, as the Supreme Court mandated us to do. Because Rahimi concerned a statute that comes within the general category of regulation of firearm possession by “dangerous people,” it has some application to the constitutional attack on the licensing provisions of the CCIA. It has no direct bearing, however, on regulations of the possession of firearms in “sensitive locations,” such as those discussed in the following pages. Its principal relevance, see supra Background § III.E, is to reinforce Bruen’s caution that the search for historical analogues is not a quest for a “historical twin,” Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1898 (quoting Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111). Because we had already faithfully applied that logic, we have had limited occasion to make substantive changes to this portion of this opinion, other than incorporating support from Rahimi.
60. Cecile relies on Does 1-10 v. Suffolk County, N.Y., No. 21-1658, 2022 WL 2678876 (2d Cir. July 12, 2022) (summary order), to urge this higher bar for standing. In Does 1-10, the defendant county informed the plaintiffs that their guns were prohibited and that they “ ‘may be subject to arrest and criminal charges’ if they ‘fail to present the weapon’ ” to the police within fifteen days. Id. at *3. But, since the county did not follow up on those warnings for over a year, and there was no evidence that “any purchaser of the [gun in question] ha[d] been arrested or had their firearm forcibly confiscated,” we decided by summary order that the plaintiffs failed to “allege[ ] that they are at an imminent risk of suffering an injury in fact.” Id. However, “[t]he identification of a credible threat sufficient to satisfy the imminence requirement of injury in fact necessarily depends on the particular circumstances at issue,” Knife Rights, 802 F.3d at 384, and Does 1-10 presented significantly different facts than those now before us.
61. Many of these announcements explained that enforcement would not be vigorous or proactive, and others suggested that the law was contrary to the speaker's personal preference. But reluctant or not, statements that the law will be enforced cannot be construed as disavowals of enforcement or otherwise used to rebut the presumption that the government enforces its laws.
62. Some Plaintiffs allege specific facts heightening their likelihood of arrest for certain intended violations. Mann alleges that a member of his congregation is a local law enforcement officer, J.A. 179 (Mann Decl. ¶ 23); Terrille explains that he is particularly likely to be arrested for possessing a gun at airports when he goes through TSA screening, J.A. 189, 194 (Terrille Decl. ¶¶ 9, 22); and Johnson notes that he often encounters state Environmental Conservation Officers while fishing, increasing the chance of arrest for carrying a gun in state parks, J.A. 142 (Johnson Decl. ¶ 24). Those claims are thus on safer footing, but we need not decide how much safer given our conclusion that, even without those additional allegations, Plaintiffs have stated a credible threat of prosecution.
63. Plaintiff Leslie Leman asserted standing to challenge this provision (and nearly every other sensitive location restriction) on the basis that he regularly carries his personal firearm in his work as a volunteer firefighter and may be called to respond to various sensitive locations. The district court rejected this theory of injury-in-fact as impermissibly speculative. See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 262. Since Plaintiffs do not dispute that conclusion, any argument as to Leman's standing is forfeited. “Although parties cannot waive arguments against jurisdiction, they are more than free to waive (or forfeit) arguments for it.” Taylor v. Pilot Corp., 955 F.3d 572, 582 (6th Cir. 2020) (Thapar, J., concurring in part) (collecting cases).
64. For this reason, nothing we say here purports to bind New York state courts when interpreting § 265.01-e in cases properly before them. This case presents exclusively federal questions, and we would not presume to tell New York courts what a New York criminal statute means or to ignore a state court's interpretation of the statute if one exists. But since we know of no relevant New York case law, of necessity we strike out on our own.
65. The district court held that the Second Amendment covered the conduct proscribed by § 265.01-e(2)(b) “except to the extent that the places at issue in th[e] regulation” were not open to the public as defined by New York state law. Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 316. Thus, the district court's injunction did not prohibit the State from enforcing § 265.01-e(2)(b) in non-public areas of behavioral health or substance dependence treatment centers.
66. Contrary to the district court's conclusion, the percentage of the national population—six percent—living in Massachusetts, Rhode Island, and Maine at the time of the statutes’ passage was significant compared to that deemed unrepresentative in Bruen. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 67, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“The exceptional nature of these western restrictions is all the more apparent when one considers the miniscule territorial populations [about two-thirds of 1%] who would have lived under them.”).
67. The district court did not question the conventionality or representativeness of the State's other group of analogous regulations—those prohibiting firearms in schools—nor do we. The Supreme Court has already determined that such regulations are well-established and representative. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (noting “Heller’s discussion of ‘longstanding’ laws forbidding the carrying of firearms in sensitive places such as schools” (internal quotation marks omitted)).
68. Though taking issue with these laws’ fit as analogues for § 265.01-e(2)(b), Plaintiffs do not dispute this characterization of the statutes’ purpose, and the district court accepted it.
69. Again, though taking issue with their fit as analogues for § 265.01-e(2)(b), Appellees do not dispute that 18th- and 19th-century laws prohibiting guns in schools, which the State provided as examples of the more general tradition of prohibiting firearms in places frequented by vulnerable people, were motivated by the need to protect children. Nor do Plaintiffs dispute that children are a vulnerable population.
70. We also find historical support for § 265.01-e(2)(b) in the fact that these laws tended to not only prohibit guns in school rooms, i.e., spaces frequented by vulnerable children, but also anywhere people “assemble[ ] for educational, literary or social purposes.” J.A. 602 (1870 Tex. Gen. Laws 63, ch. 46); see also J.A. 611 (1883 Mo. Sess. Laws 76) (same); J.A. 617 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 17, § 3) (same for “amusement or for educational or scientific purposes”); J.A. 620 (1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, § 7) (same for “educational purposes”). The modern hospitals that provide some of today's behavioral care and substance disorder services provide “the principal clinical-education settings for medical students enrolled in medical schools.” Amicus Br. on behalf of Greater New York Hospital Assoc., at 14, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
71. Our finding that individuals with behavioral and substance abuse disorders have historically been considered a “vulnerable population” who cannot be trusted near weapons finds further support in the regulation of weapons by many publicly operated asylums for the mentally ill. Such rules appear to have been motivated by the fear that patients would obtain possession of such weapons and thereby injure themselves or others. Utica Asylum and Buffalo State Asylum (both state facilities) prohibited “attendant[s]” from “plac[ing] in the hands of a patient, or leav[ing] within his reach,” certain weapons. See Rules, Regs. & By-Laws of the N.Y. State Lunatic Asylum at Utica, Duty of Attendants to Patients § 7 (1840); Rules & Regs. Governing the Buffalo State Asylum, Duty of Attendants to Patients § 7 (1888). During Reconstruction and shortly after, many other government-run institutions adopted the same rule. See Rules for the Missouri State Lunatic Asylum § 8 (1870); Rules, Regulations, and By-Laws of the Arkansas Lunatic Asylum, Little Rock § 8 (1883); Rules & Regulations of State Lunatic Asylum No. 3, Nevada, Mo. § 129 (1887).
72. The State need not always provide evidence that a group has historically been considered vulnerable every time it wishes to regulate firearms to protect that group. An even “more nuanced approach” would be appropriate were the regulation to address a vulnerable group or setting that did not exist at the time of Reconstruction or the Founding. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 27, 142 S.Ct. 2111. But, as the State itself argues and depends on here, those with behavioral and substance use disorders have long been considered a vulnerable group. See id. at 26, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (requiring more where “a challenged regulation addresses a general societal problem that has persisted since the 18th century”).
73. The district court also enjoined the place of worship provision on the ground that it was “too close to infringing on one's First Amendment right to participate in congregate religious services.” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 322. No Plaintiff had requested injunctive relief on this ground, nor did the district court make findings as to whether any Plaintiff's free exercise was inhibited by the place of worship provision; we therefore do not consider it a basis for the injunction. See generally Mem. of Law in Supp. of Preliminary Inj., Antonyuk v. Nigrelli, No. 22-cv-00986 (Sept. 22, 2022), ECF No. 6-1 (not specifically challenging the place of worship provision); Reply Mem. in Supp. of Preliminary Inj. at 29–31, supra (Oct. 22, 2022), ECF No. 69 (advancing only Second Amendment arguments against it).
74. The Plaintiffs’ post-amendment submission to this Court under Federal Rule of Appellate Procedure 28(j) seems to confirm this analysis. It calls the new grant of authority to church leaders “a welcome change” and argues only that “other provisions” of the CCIA keep Mann from keeping weapons in the church (and that the statute amounts to compelled speech), objections addressed elsewhere in this opinion. See Appellees’ May 10, 2023 Letter at 1–2, ECF No. 378.
75. Our prior consolidated opinion left intact the preliminary injunction issued by the district court in Spencer, which prohibited enforcement of § 265.01-e(2)(c) against plaintiffs in that case. See Antonyuk v. Chiumento, 89 F.4th 271, 352 (2d Cir. 2023). Nothing in this amended opinion in Antonyuk should be construed as having any effect on the preliminary injunction issued and upheld in Spencer.
76. The State defendants do not challenge the district court's holding that various Plaintiffs had standing as to public parks, and we see no impediment to standing.
77. See Fourth Annual Report of The Board of Commissioners of The Central Park (Jan. 1861); First Annual Report of The Commissioners of Fairmount Park (Philadelphia), Supplement § 21(II) (1869); Rules and Regulations of The Public Parks and Grounds of The City of Saint Paul (1888); 1895 Mich. Pub. Acts 596; Chicago Muni. Code art. 43 (1881); Salt Lake City, Revised Ordinances ch. 27 (1888), Tower Grove Park Bd. of Comm'rs, Rules and Regulations, in David H. MacAdam, Tower Grove Park of the City of St. Louis (1883); Pittsburgh Gen. Ordinances, Bureau of Parks, p. 496 (2d ed. 1897).
78. The district court determined that § 265.01-e’s prohibition on carriage in playgrounds was consistent with history and tradition and did not issue an injunction as to that aspect of the regulation. That determination is not on review in this appeal. No Plaintiff has appealed from that ruling, so it is not before us for review.
79. See Darrell A.H. Miller, Constitutional Conflict and Sensitive Places, 28 WM. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 459, 475–76 (2019) (noting that “First Amendment institution[s]” are designed for the “right to peaceably assemble” and that regulations to ensure such peaceable assembly have both “a long history in Anglo-American jurisprudence,” and have historically been “bolstered by general prohibitions on armaments in places like fairs and markets—places one would think part of the ‘immemorial’ custom of public forums”).
80. Insofar as the State relies on the tradition of regulating firearms in places frequented by children as an analogue for § 265.01-e(2)(d), Bruen tells us that tradition is well-established and representative. See 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
81. Our own research reveals another such jurisdiction. See, e.g., An Act for Punishment of Crimes and Offences, within the District of Columbia, § 40 (1816), available at https://rb.gy/7q0cv [https://perma.cc/88PB-Y654] (prohibiting going or riding “armed by night nor day, in fairs or markets, or in other places, in terror of the county”).
82. Two observations regarding these Founding-era statutes are warranted. First, while the Virginia statute differed from the medieval English Northampton statute in that it prohibited conduct and not simply carriage, i.e., bearing arms in “terror” of the county, the North Carolina statute, like the Northampton statute, appears to have prohibited firearm carriage in general at fairs and markets regardless of conduct. And, as we will elaborate below, the tradition of regulating firearms in quintessentially crowded places evolved in the direction of the North Carolina statute, i.e., the prohibition of carriage without any reference to conduct. Thus, despite the Virginia law's “in terror of the county” language, we do not interpret the national tradition of regulating firearms in quintessentially crowded places to require a conduct element. Second, though Bruen rejected the medieval Northampton statute, it did so within the context in which that statute was offered: as an analogue supporting a carriage ban in public generally. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 40, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (explaining that the state had offered the Northampton statute as a “sweeping restriction on public carry of self-defense weapons”). In sum, Bruen addressed the statute in a different context; nor was the statute discounted by Bruen for the analogical purpose for which we rely upon it here. See id. at 45, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (noting that historical evidence establishes that the Northampton statute was “no obstacle to public carry for self-defense” generally but not addressing the more specific prohibitions in the statute such as carriage in fairs and markets). We therefore do not take Bruen’s observations regarding the Northampton statute to run contrary to our more limited conclusions here. See Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1902 (“The conclusion that focused [firearm] regulations ․ are not a historical analogue for a broad prohibitory regime like New York's [in Bruen] does not mean that they cannot be an appropriate analogue for a narrow one.”).
83. Though the Supreme Court discounted English as an outlier in Bruen, it did so only insofar as English held that the state could lawfully restrict carriage to those with “reasonable grounds for fearing an unlawful attack.” Bruen, 597 U.S. at 64, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (quoting 1871 Tex. Gen. Laws ch. 34). New York had offered English and the underlying statute as an analogue to the special need requirement at issue in Bruen. Id. Accordingly, we do not understand Bruen to have cast doubt on English’s holding as to the 1871 Texas statute's separate restriction relating to public assembly. Nor do we find independent reason to doubt that English’s holding as to public assembly restrictions is consistent with the Nation's tradition. Whereas Texas's historical “reasonable grounds” requirement was an outlier in that it went against the tradition of a majority of the Nation and was only replicated by one other state, see id. at 64–65, 142 S.Ct. 2111, the public assembly restriction is consistent with the national tradition and existed in many states. See also Rahimi, 144 S. Ct. at 1902 (“The conclusion that focused [firearm] regulations ․ are not a historical analogue for a broad prohibitory regime like New York's [in Bruen] does not mean that they cannot be an appropriate analogue for a narrow one.”).
84. The 1790 Census counted approximately 3.3 million Americans, of whom 747,610 lived in Virginia and 393,751 in North Carolina. Dept. of Interior, Compendium of Eleventh Census: 1890, 3 tbl. 1 (1892).
85. The 1890 Census counted approximately 62.6 million Americans. Dept. of Interior, Compendium of Eleventh Census: 1890, 2 tbl. 1 (1892). The combined population of Virginia, North Carolina, Texas, Missouri, Tennessee, Oklahoma, and Arizona was approximately 9.3 million. Id.
86. Though the historical analogues here are “relatively simple to draw,” the relative novelty of public parks as institutions also justifies a flexible approach under Bruen. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 27, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (explaining that historical and societal “changes may require a more nuanced approach”).
87. See Margaret Walls, Parks and Recreation in the United States: Local Park Systems 1, Resources for the Future (June 2009).
88. See also Frederick Law Olmsted, A Consideration of the Justifying Value of a Public Park 7–8 (1881) (“Twenty-five years ago we had no parks, park-like or otherwise”).
89. See David Schuyler, The New Urban Landscape: The Redefinition of City Form In Nineteenth-Century America 1–8 (1988) (describing the emergence of a “new urban landscape” whose proponents urged establishment of public parks to “create[ ] communal spaces” where “rural scenery might sooth the ‘nerves and mind’ of visitors’ ”); see also Everytown for Gun Safety Br. at 26–27.
90. By 1897, approximately 5.2 million Americans lived in these eight cities under municipal regulations that would have prohibited carriage of firearms in a city's public parks. See Dept. of Interior, Compendium of Eleventh Census: 1890, 442–52 tbl. 5 (1892). And, as amici point out, see Everytown for Gun Safety Br. at 21–22, it is likely that even more urban park regulations will emerge at a later point in the litigation regarding the CCIA. See also The City of New York Br. at 15 n.22 (listing additional city ordinances prohibiting firearms in public urban parks).
91. It also failed to consider the 1869 Tennessee Law prohibiting deadly weapons in any “fair, race course, or public assembly of people.” J.A. 605 (1869 Tenn. Pub. Acts. 23). Thus, the only state laws it considered were the 1870 Texas and 1883 Missouri laws.
92. Because the tradition of regulating firearms in often-crowded public squares supports the State's burden as to § 265.01-e’s regulation of firearms in urban parks, we need not rely on the tradition of regulating firearms in places frequented by children.
93. The State does not seriously argue that the tradition of regulating firearms in places frequented by children justifies § 265.01-e’s applicability to rural parks.
94. Roy Rosenzweig and Elizabeth Blackmar, The Park and The People: A History of Central Park 4 (1992).
95. David Schuyler, The New Urban Landscape: The Redefinition of City Form In Nineteenth-Century America 1–8 (1988)
96. Shoked, supra, at 1556–57.
97. Effective May 3, 2023, the New York legislature amended § 265.01-e(2)(d) by adding the following limiting language: “provided that for the purposes of this section a ‘public park’ shall not include (i) any privately held land within a public park not dedicated to public use or (ii) the forest preserve as defined in subdivision six of section 9-0101 of the environmental conservation law.” Although we express no opinion on whether the provision as amended conforms with the Second Amendment principles we have articulated here, we note that the legislature has considered the constitutional implications of the public parks provision and has taken affirmative steps to address them.
98. The Philadelphia Zoo, which bills itself as the first public zoo in the United States, was chartered in 1859, but due to the intervening Civil War, did not open until 1874. See About the Zoo, Philadelphia Zoo, available at https://www.philadelphiazoo.org/about-the-zoo/ [https://perma.cc/7795-NX2A]. A few other urban zoos, including New York's Central Park Zoo, have claims to have opened sooner than 1874, but we nonetheless have identified no public zoo that claims to have opened before the Civil War. The drafters of the Second Amendment presumably had no particular intentions with respect to the right to carry firearms in any place remotely resembling today's Bronx Zoo.
99. The only case cited in Bruen for the proposition that “some” territorial laws were held unconstitutional is In re Brickey, 8 Idaho 597, 70 P. 609 (1902). 597 U.S. at 69, 142 S.Ct. 2111. That one-paragraph opinion invalidated a statute that apparently prohibited the carriage of deadly weapons within the limits of a city, town, or village (the statute is only paraphrased, not quoted, in the brief decision). In re Brickey, 8 Idaho at 897, 72 P. 671. Far from suggesting the unconstitutionality even of New York's Sullivan Law, let alone laws addressing sensitive places, the Idaho Supreme Court merely noted that the state legislature had the power to regulate arms-bearing, but not totally to prohibit it, specifically stating that “[a] statute prohibiting the carrying of concealed deadly weapons [which the court characterized as ‘a pernicious practice’] would be a proper exercise of the police power of the state.” Id. (emphasis added).
100. All of the State's analogues were still in effect in 1889, and the population of the six states from which the State draws its historical analogues was approximately 6 million. Dept. of Interior, Compendium of Eleventh Census: 1890, 2 tbl. 1 (1892). The population of the United States that same year was approximately 62.6 million. Id.
101. As to the State's reliance on the tradition of regulating firearms in crowded places, we have already addressed this regulatory tradition, see supra Sensitive Locations §§ III.B.2 & III.B.3, and found that it is well-established and representative. We further note here that the 1889 Arizona and 1890 Oklahoma statutes prohibiting carriage in liquor-serving and -selling establishments likewise prohibited firearms in social parties, gatherings, and ball rooms. J.A. 617 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 17); id. at 621 (1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, § 7); see also id. at 602, 141 S.Ct. 2373 (1870 Tex. Gen. Laws 73) (prohibiting carriage in social gatherings, parties, and ball rooms).
102. Because the regulation is consistent with both categories, we need not decide whether the historical analogues for regulating firearms in crowded places would alone justify § 265.01-e(2)(o).
103. In fact, though the district court made much of the distinction between regulating place versus behavior, 19th century case law reveals that at least some state courts analogized regulating behavior to regulating places in finding behavior-based regulations constitutional. See Shelby, 2 S.W. at 469 (observing that “no good reason” exists for distinguishing between the constitutionality of the legislature's regulation of firearms in “time and place” and the regulation “of the person who carries such weapons”).
104. A showing that he had done so would likely have supported injury-in-fact: the statute of limitations on violating § 265.01-e will not run for several years, see N.Y. C.P.L. § 30.10(2)(b) (establishing five-year limitations period for felonies), so Terrille might still have claimed a credible threat of prosecution. But even though the State argued mootness here and in the district court, Terrille has done nothing to supplement his averments.
105. The district court seems to have accepted this characterization sub silentio. Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 286 (“Plaintiff Terrille has sworn that he has frequently carried concealed in ․ conference centers and banquet halls, and will do so again ․”). In fact, as discussed below, Terrille's affidavit made no such statement.
106. See J.A. 191–92 (Terrille Decl. ¶ 16) (“I plan to attend the upcoming NEACA Polish Community Center Gun Show, to occur on October 8-9, 2022, in Albany. The gun show is hosted by The Polish Community Center, which describes itself as ‘a conference center, banquet hall & wedding venue in Albany, NY.’ ․ I currently plan to attend the upcoming Albany gun show, and I intend to carry my firearm with me when I do, in violation of the CCIA[.]”).
107. This is why Terrille's claim is moot but Corey Johnson's claim is not. Johnson averred that he intended to visit the Rosamond Gifford Zoo “within the next 90 days” and that he and his wife regularly visit the zoo “once or twice every fall” in order to see certain creatures. J.A. 139–40 (Johnson Decl. ¶ 17).
108. The district court appears to have slightly misunderstood Mann's claim as being that his church contains a “banquet hall.” See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 286. Instead, Mann alleged that the church itself constitutes a “banquet hall,” and Plaintiffs have not advanced the district court's interpretation here. We do not decide whether a separate “hall” within a church might qualify under the statute.
109. See Banquet, Merriam-Webster.com Dictionary, available at https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/banquet [https://perma.cc/H3WV-LKBZ] (“a sumptuous feast, especially [ ] an elaborate and often ceremonious meal for numerous people often in honor of a person; a meal held in recognition of some occasion or achievement”)
110. See Hall, Oxford English Dictionary, available at https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/6129098993 [https://perma.cc/G846-QK8V] (“[a] large room or building for the transaction of public business ․ or any public assemblies, meetings, or entertainments,” or in this case, banquets).
111. J.A. 605–06 (1869 Tenn. Pub. Acts 23–24) (1869 Tennessee law prohibiting carriage of deadly weapons by “any person attending any fair, race course, or other public assembly of people”); id. at 611 (1883 Mo. Sess. Laws 76) (1883 Missouri law prohibiting weapons “where people are assembled for educational, literary or social purposes”); id. at 617 (1889 Ariz. Sess. Laws 17) (1889 Arizona law prohibiting dangerous weapons “where persons are assembled for amusement or for educational or scientific purposes, or into any circus, show or public exhibition of any kind, or into a ball room, social party or social gathering”); id. at 621 (1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, § 7) (1890 Oklahoma law prohibiting carriage in places “where persons are assembled for ․ amusement, or for educational or scientific purposes, or into any circus, show or public exhibition of any kind, or into any ball room, or to any social party or social gathering”).
112. We do not take the “silence” of the historical record, as it has so far been developed, on carriage restrictions specific to theaters to indicate that regulating firearms in theaters is unconstitutional. First, the record also lacks any affirmative evidence that gun regulations in theaters were considered unlawful. Second, such regulations may not have been necessary given that the statutes prohibiting carriage at social, amusement, literary, or educational gatherings appear to have naturally covered theaters.
113. Even if the Tennessee and Texas laws were the only laws cited by the State at this point in the litigation, it is not clear to us that the relative populations of those states would support the district court's conclusion that the laws were neither well-established nor representative. As we have mentioned elsewhere, Bruen discounted analogical statutes that covered less than 1 percent of the American population and ran directly contrary to a majority of the country at the time. See Bruen, 597 U.S. at 68, 142 S.Ct. 2111. According to the district court itself, the historical analogues from Tennessee and Texas covered 5.3 percent of the population.
114. The district court considered the North Carolina statute in a footnote and dismissed it for “similar reasons (i.e., the lack of a reasonable analogy to terroristic behavior ․).” Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 334 n.117. Yet, unlike the Virginia statute, the North Carolina statute did not ban firearms based on terroristic conduct, it banned all carriage in fairs and markets. See Collection of Statutes of the Parliament of England in Force in the State of North-Carolina, pp. 60–61, ch. 3 (F. Martin Ed. 1792).
115. As we discussed above, see Sensitive Locations § III.B.2.a, Bruen’s discussion of the Northampton statute is not relevant here because it considered that law when offered as an analogue for a broad prohibition on public carriage generally, not as offered here for a specific prohibition on carriage in confined, crowded spaces. Bruen, 597 U.S. at 40–46, 142 S.Ct. 2111.
116. The district court's logic suggests that, because enhanced licensure requirements purportedly diminish the need for carriage restrictions, carriage restrictions are inconsistent with their historical analogues if those analogues were enacted at times with lesser licensing requirements. By this logic, a state must choose between regulating licensure and regulating carriage even if both carriage and licensure requirements are constitutional. By its own terms, Bruen does not so tie states’ hands. See 597 U.S. at 30, 142 S.Ct. 2111 (“[T]he Second Amendment is [not] a regulatory straightjacket[.]”).
117. Plaintiffs Johnson and Terrille alleged an intention to attend political protests in the future, but the district court found those allegations insufficiently specific and/or imminent for Article III standing. See Antonyuk, 639 F. Supp. 3d at 389–91. Since Plaintiffs do not challenge this determination on appeal, the argument is forfeited, and we do not consider it.
118. As with the “Sensitive Locations” provisions discussed above, Rahimi has no direct bearing on the provisions discussed in this portion of our prior opinion, and accordingly, after reconsidering our conclusions in light of Rahimi, we conclude that that decision requires no substantive change to this part of our opinion.
119. See Ruqaiyah Zarouk, Mapping Private vs. Public Land in the United States, Am. Geographical Soc'y, available at https://ubique.americangeo.org/map-of-the-week/mapof-the-week-mapping-private-vs-public-land-in-the-united-states/ [https://perma.cc/4GFS-UPJL].
120. In our prior consolidated opinion, we reviewed the merits analysis of the district court in Christian, one of the cases related to Antonyuk, before reviewing the Antonyuk court's analysis of the same provision. The plaintiffs in Christian brought a challenge to the restricted location provision only as that provision applied to private property open to the public. We concluded, as we do now, that the restricted location provision was unconstitutional as applied to such property. Antonyuk, 89 F.4th at 386.The plaintiffs in Antonyuk brought a facial challenge to the provision, and the district court enjoined the provision as it applied both to property open to the public and property closed to the public. As noted above, however, the Antonyuk district court's Second Amendment analysis of the provision focused primarily on public property open to the public. To align with our conclusions about the restricted location provision in Christian, instead of vacating the Antonyuk injunction as to that provision, we modified it to conform to the injunction of that provision in Christian. Id. at 387. Because reconsideration of Antonyuk in light of the Supreme Court's decision in Rahimi does not bear on our conclusions about the restricted location provision and because our opinion about the provision in Christian remains good law as it pertains to that case, we again conclude that the provision is unconstitutional as applied to private property open to the public and modify the district court's injunction to that effect.
121. Although, as discussed below, the district court erred in relying only on its analysis of property open to the public to enjoin enforcement of § 265.01-d for property closed to the public, it did not err in reasoning that the Second Amendment protects a general right to public carriage.
122. Though the remaining statutes are not by their own terms aimed at deterring poaching, the State has placed no evidence in the record regarding whether the motivation behind these statutes was in line with the motivation behind § 265.01-d.
123. See State v. Hopping, 18 N.J.L. 423, 424 (1842) (“improvements is a legal and technical word, and means inclosures, or inclosed fields: lands fenced in, and thus withdrawn and separated from the wastes or common lands”); Land, Webster's Am. Dictionary of the English Lang. (1828), available at https://webstersdictionary1828.com/Dictionary/land [https://perma.cc/3A9Y-SKWQ] (“Any small portion of the superficial part of the earth or ground. We speak of the quantity of land in a manor. Five hundred acres of land is a large farm.”); Plantation, Webster's Am. Dictionary of the English Lang. (1828), available at https://webstersdictionary1828.com/Dictionary/plantation [https://perma.cc/6DG8-QTFQ] (“In the United States and the West Indies, a cultivated estate; a farm.”); Premises, Webster's Am. Dictionary of the English Lang. (1828), available at https://webstersdictionary1828.com/Dictionary/premises [https://perma.cc/AKG7-DEL7] (“In law, land or other things mentioned in the preceding part of a deed.”). On the preliminary record here, we are therefore unable to agree with the Ninth Circuit in Wolford, 116 F.4th at 995, that any of these statutes “applied to all private property,” regardless of whether the property was open to the public, so as to be a sufficient analog for the provision at issue here.
124. The State's apparent willingness to adopt the district court's approach, by declining to draw a distinction in § 265.01-d or the Second Amendment between property open to the public and property not open to the public, does not alter our analysis. The State cannot waive the rule that courts cannot facially invalidate a statute unless it is unconstitutional in all of its applications because this rule is a necessary “exercis[e] of judicial restraint” without which a facial challenge would “run contrary to the fundamental principle of judicial restraint.” Wash. State Grange, 552 U.S. at 450, 128 S.Ct. 1184. This requirement of total facial invalidity is a salutary and necessary limit on judicial power, not a protection for the defendant in constitutional litigation. See id. (“[J]udicial restraint in a facial challenge frees the Court not only from unnecessary pronouncement on constitutional issues, but also from premature interpretations of statutes in areas where their constitutional application might be cloudy.” (internal quotation marks omitted)).
125. Because we conclude that the restricted locations provision of the CCIA violates the Second Amendment, we need not address Plaintiffs’ contention that the provision violates the First Amendment by requiring owners of private property generally open to the public who wish to welcome visitors carrying concealed firearms to say so.We confess to a certain skepticism about that claim. If private property owners are free either to grant or refuse access to visitors, a default rule that consent is presumed would compel speech on the part of proprietors to forbid firearms just as much as the CCIA requires speech from those who would welcome them. That someone will need to express his wishes regardless of the chosen default rule is just a fact of life, and not a violation of the First Amendment. Plaintiffs’ argument, however, points up a further reason why the restricted location default rule impinges on the Second Amendment. If that Amendment grants a presumptive right to carry firearms in public places, and the State must—even by its silence—create a default rule as to the presumption to be applied when the owner of property open to the public does not express a preference, the choice of a default rule that discriminates against the Second Amendment right is inherently problematic.
126. We emphasize that we are here reviewing facial challenges to these provisions at a very early stage of this litigation. A preliminary injunction is not a full merits decision, but rather addresses only the “likelihood of success on the merits.” Salinger v. Colting, 607 F.3d 68, 79 (2d Cir. 2010) (emphasis added); see also Amoco Prod. Co. v. Vill. of Gambell, AK, 480 U.S. 531, 546 n.12, 107 S.Ct. 1396, 94 L.Ed.2d 542 (1987) (“The standard for a preliminary injunction is essentially the same as for a permanent injunction with the exception that the plaintiff must show a likelihood of success on the merits rather than actual success.”). Our affirmance or vacatur of the district court's injunction does not determine the ultimate constitutionality of the challenged CCIA provisions, which await further briefing, discovery, and historical analysis, both in this case as it proceeds and perhaps in other cases.
Dennis Jacobs, Gerard E. Lynch, and Eunice C. Lee, Circuit Judges:
A free source of state and federal court opinions, state laws, and the United States Code. For more information about the legal concepts addressed by these cases and statutes visit FindLaw's Learn About the Law.
Docket No: Docket Nos. 22-2908(L), 22-2972(Con)
Decided: October 24, 2024
Court: United States Court of Appeals, Second Circuit.
Search our directory by legal issue
Enter information in one or both fields (Required)
Harness the power of our directory with your own profile. Select the button below to sign up.
Learn more about FindLaw’s newsletters, including our terms of use and privacy policy.
Get help with your legal needs
FindLaw’s Learn About the Law features thousands of informational articles to help you understand your options. And if you’re ready to hire an attorney, find one in your area who can help.
Search our directory by legal issue
Enter information in one or both fields (Required)